최근 글 목록
-
- [서평] 진화의 무지개
- 와라
- 2010
-
- 개정 저작권법 시행 후 첫 ‘계정정지’ ...
- 와라
- 2010
-
- [서평] - 모두스 비벤디(지그문트 바우만)
- 와라
- 2010
-
- 나는 표절자
- 와라
- 2010
-
- [서평] 처음에는 비극으로, 다음에는 ...
- 와라
- 2010
19개의 게시물을 찾았습니다.
벤야민이 1913년에 쓴 ‘경험(Erfahrung)’이라는 글이다.
원문은 독일어이지만 내가 독일어를 못하는 관계로 영역본을 기초로 번역했다.
내가 참고한 영역본은 Havard University Press에서 나온 벤야민 선집이고(이 선집에서 이 글은 제일 처음 실려 있다), Lloyd Spencer와 Stefan Jost가 영역했다.
벤야민 영역본에는 경험(Erfahrung)과 체험(Erlebnis)이 구분되지 않고, 둘 다 Experience로 번역되어 있다고 들은 기억이 있다. 이 글에서도 경험(experience)이라는 단어만 나오고 있다. 아직 독어판과 비교해 보지 못한터라 Erlebnis도 Experience로 번역한 것인지는 잘 모르겠다. 하지만 확실한 것은 경험과 체험이 이 글에서도 (표기는 경험으로 되어 있지만, 내포된 의미를 보면)명확히 구분되고 있다는 점이다. 특히 뒷부분에서 경험으로 번역한 몇몇 부분은 체험으로 옮겨 적어야 의미가 명확해 질 듯 하다. 이 구분은 벤야민의 사상을 연구할 때 핵심적인 내용을 가진 것이므로 개념적으로 명확히 할 필요가 있다.
예를 들어 벤야민은 영상 매체가 대중에게 던지는 충격을 체험이라고 말한다. 경험에 대한 체험의 관계는, 정신분석학에서 말하는 상징계에 대한 실재의 침입과 비슷한 역할을 한다.(나는 여기서 경험=상징계, 체험=실재 라고 말하고 있는 것이 아니다) 그만큼 벤야민에게서 이 두 개념의 구분은 핵심적인 지위를 차지하고 있다는 것이다.
이래저래 떠들어도 이 글을 번역해서 올리는 것은 개인적으로 이 글을 굉장히 좋아하기 때문이다. 나태해지려할 때, 무엇인가를 시작할 때, 어떤 것이든 전환점이 필요할 때 즐겨 읽는 글이다. 내 영어(와 번역_ 실력의 미천함 때문에 읽는 사람에게 폐를 끼칠 수 있다고 생각하지만, 읽기 싫은 사람은 안 읽으면 되니 내 책임은 아니겠지... 라고 정당화해 본다. 아직 초벌 번역이라 문장이 이상한 데가 많을테니 감안하고 읽어 보시길.
추가 : 연구소의 로아님이 벤야민 독어판 전집을 가지고 있어서 비교해 본 결과, 이 글에 나오는 경험이라는 단어는 모두 Erfahrung으로 나와 있었다고 합니다(로아님 확인 감사^^). 그리고 영어로 sprit(독어 Geist)이라고 되어 있는 용어를 제가 영혼이라고 번역했는데, 보통 독어의 Geist는 영어로 spirit로 번역되는데 한글로도 정신으로 옮기는 것이 통례라고 지적해주셨습니다. 제가 영혼이라고 번역한 것들(옆에 spirit이라고 영문표기를 달아놓았습니다)은 정신(geist)라고 생각하고 읽으시면 됩니다. 다만 제가 spirit을 영혼으로 옮긴 것은 without spirit과 같은 문구가 나와서 인데, 이것을 우리말로 옮기면 '정신 없이'정도가 되서 어감상 오해의 여지가 있으리라 판단해서입니다. 정신없다는 말은 우리말에서는 관영어구처럼 쓰이기 때문에 벤야민이 쓰는 맥락과 조금 다르게 다가올수 있으니까요. 어쨋든 이런 점 주의해서 읽으시면 될듯 합니다.
................................................................................................................
경험(Experience, Erfahrung, 1913) - 발터 벤야민 책임을 위한 투쟁에서, 우리는 가면 쓴 이들에 맞서 싸운다. 어른들의 가면은 ‘경험’이라고 불린다. 그것은 표현할 수도, 이해할 수도 없고 항상 동일하다. 어른은 항상 이미 모든 것을 경험했다: 젊음, 이상, 희망, 여성. 그것은 모두 환상이다. - 종종 우리는 겁먹거나 괴로워한다. 아마도 그는 옳다. 우리의 반론은 무엇이 될 수 있을까? 우리는 아직 아무것도 경험하지 못했다.[우리는 아직 아무것도 알지 못한다]
그러나, 가면을 벗기려 시도해 보자. 어른이 경험한 것은 무엇일까? 그가 우리에게 증명하려는 것은 무엇일까? 그것은 결국, 그 역시 한 때 젊었었다는 것, 그 역시 우리가 원하는 것을 원했었다는 것, 그 역시 그의 부모에 대한 믿음을 거절당했다는 것, 그러나 그들이 옳다는 것을 삶이 그에게 가르쳐 주었다는 것이다. 이렇게 말해보자, 그는 훌륭한 방식으로 웃는다. 우리도 그렇게 할 것이다. - 그는 미리 우리가 살아갈 (진지한 삶의 기나긴 엄숙함 이전에 오는)철없는 환희의 세월들을 평가 절하한다. 이렇게 선한 것, 교화된 것. 우리는 우리에게 짧은 젊음을 허용조차 하지 않는 씁쓸함(bitterness)이라는 다른 선생들을 알고 있다: 진지하고 엄한, 그들은 우리들을 삶의 고역으로 바로 밀어 넣는다. 양자의 태도는 우리의 세월들을 평가절하하고 파괴한다. 게다가 감정에 엄습 당한다: 우리의 젊음은 짧은 밤이다(환희로 채워라); 그것은, 타협의 세월들, 관념의 빈곤, 그리고 활력의 결여와 같은, 거대한 ‘경험’에 뒤따라 올 것이다. 그런 것이 인생이다. 그것이 어른들이 우리에게 말하는 것, 그리고 그들이 경험한 것이다.
그렇다, 그것이 그들의 경험이다. 이 하나, 결코 다를 것 없는: 인생의 무의미함. 그것은 잔인하다. 그들이 우리에게 훌륭하거나 새롭거나 진취적인 어떤 것을 장려한 적이 있던가? 아니다, 명확히도 이것들은 경험될 수 없는 것이기 때문이다. 모든 의미 - 진실된 것, 선한 것, 아름다운 것 - 는 그 자신 안에 지평을 수립한다. 그럼, 경험이 상징하는 것은 무엇인가? - 그리고 이 속에 비밀이 놓여 있다. 왜냐하면 그는 결코 위대한 것, 의미 있는 것에 시선을 두지 않기 때문이다. 속물(the philistine)은 경험을 그의 복음으로 취한다. 그것은 그에게 인생의 공통성에 관한 메시지가 된다. 그러나 그는 결코 거기에 경험과는 다른, 우리가 추구해야 할 경험될 수 없는 가치 같은 것이 존재한다는 점을 포착하지 못한다.
속물에게는 왜 삶이 의미도, 이유도 없는 것일까? 그는 (다른 것은 모른채) 경험만을 알기 때문이다. 그는 영혼(sprit)의 부재와 황량함 자체이기 때문이다. 그리고 그는 공통적인 것 그리고 항상-이미-낡은 것 외에 다른 것과 내적 관계를 가지지 않기 때문이다.
하지만, 우리는(경험이 우리에게 줄 수도 앗아갈 수도 없는)다른 무엇인가를 알고 있다: 비록 지금까지의 모든 사상들이 잘못된 것이라 해도, 진리가 존재한다는 것을 알고 있다. 혹은 비록 아직까지 그 누구도 완료하지 못했다 해도 지속되어야 하는 충실함을 알고 있다. 그런 것들은 경험을 통해 우리에게 전달 될 수 없는 것들이다. 그러나 나이든 이들은, 피곤한 몸짓과 초연한 절망으로, 모든 것에서 옳은 것일까? 다시 말해, 우리가 경험한 것은 후회일 것이고, 초석이 되는 용기, 희망, 의미는 경험될 수 없는 것이라는게 옳은 것일까? 그렇다면 영혼(spirit)은 자유로울 게다. 하지만 또 다시 삶은 쇠약해질 것이다. (경험의 총체인)삶은 위안 없는 것일 뿐이므로.
그러나, 우리는 결코 그런 물음들을 이해할 수 없다. 그럼에도 우리는 영혼(spirit)과 함께 그런 낯선 삶을 인도해야 하는가? 그들의 나태한 자아는 바위에 부딪히는 파도 같은 삶에 의해 농락당해야 하는가? 아니다. 우리 각자의 경험은 값어치가 있다. 우리 자신은 우리만의 영혼으로 그것들에 값어치를 투여한다 - 경솔한 그는 착오에 만족한다. 그는 탐색자에게 “너는 절대 진리를 찾을 수 없어”라고 외친다. “그것이 내 경험이야.” 그러나 탐색자에게 ‘착오는 진리에 이르는 유일한 길이다’(스피노자). 다만 어리석은 자에게 그것은 의미와 영혼이 결여된 경험이다. 아마 맞서는 자에게 경험은 고통스럽겠지만, 그를 절망으로 인도하지 않을 것이다.
어째든, 그는 결코 덤덤하게 포기하지도, 속물의 리듬에 마취되지도 않을 것이다. 당신은 속물에게 ‘(당신은)모든 새로운 무의미함 속에서 기쁨만 느낄 수 있다’고 지적할 것이다. 그는 옳음 속에 잔존한다. 그는 스스로 재-확신 한다: 영혼(spirit)은 실제로 존재하지 않는다고. 하지만 ‘영혼’ 앞에서 위대한 경외와 가혹한 복종을 요구하는 이는 없다. 왜냐하면 만약 그가 비판적이 된다면, 그도 그가 만들 수 없는 것을 창조해야 하기 때문이다. (그의 의지에 반해 그가 겪는) 영혼의 경험 조차도 그에게는 무관심한 것이 된다.
그에게 말하라
그가 한 사람의 남자/어른(a man)이 되었을 때
그는 그의 젊음의 꿈을 우러러보아야 한다는 것을.
(프리드리히 실러, 돈 카를로스 중)
속물에게는 “그의 젊음의 꿈”만큼 꺼림칙한 것이 없다. 그리고 대부분의 시간 동안, 감성적임은 그의 혐오의 보호적 위장이다. 왜냐하면 그의 꿈에서 그에게 나타난 것은 (모두에게 그렇듯이, 예전의 그를 부르는)영혼의 목소리이기 때문이다. 그것은 젊음이 끊임없이 그리고 불길하게 그를 일깨우는 어떤 것이다. 그것이 그가 젊음에 적대적인 이유이다. 그는 어린 사람들에게 그런 무서움(압도적인 경험)에 대해 말하고, 그들에게 그들 자신을 비웃도록 가르친다. 특히 영혼 없이 경험하는 것이 편하다고, 만약 되찾을 수 없다면.
다시: 우리는 다른 경험을 알고 있다. 그것은 영혼에 적대적이고, 피어나는 꿈을 파괴할 수 있다. 그럼에도 불구하고 그것은 가장 아름답고, 가장 범접할수 없고, 가장 직접적이다. 왜냐하면 우리가 젊음을 유지하는 동안 결코 영혼 없이 존재할 수 없기 때문이다. 짜라투스트라가 말했듯이, 개인은 방황의 끝에서만 자신을 경험할 수 있다. 속물은 그만의 ‘경험’을 가지고 있다; 그것은 영속적인 영혼없음(spiritlessness) 중의 하나이다. 젊음은 영혼을 경험한다. 그리고 그가 덜 쉽게 위대함을 얻을수록, 방황속에서, 사람들 속에서 영혼과 더 많이 대면할 것이다. - 그가 남자/어른이 되었을 때, 젊음은 측은하게 될 것이다. 속물은 불관용적이다.
폭력론
-소렐, 벤야민, 데리다, 파농, 아렌트의 논의를 중심으로
박홍규 • 영남대학교 교수/ 법학
1. 폭력의 뜻
국어사전에서 폭력이란 ‘함부로 난폭한 행동을 하는 힘’으로 풀이되고, ‘폭력을 써서 소기의 목적을 달성하려는 단체’가 폭력단이라고 설명된다. 그리고 폭력주의자는 테러리스트, 폭력주의는 테러리즘이라고 한다. 즉 폭력은 테러라는 것이 국어사전의 이해이다. 그러나 국어사전에서는 폭력의 영어를 force라고 표기한다. 일반적으로 영어에서 폭력은 테러(terror)도 힘(force)도 아닌 violence를 말한다. 영어사전에서 violence란 ‘비공인의 완력이나 물리적 힘에 의한 강습’을 뜻하고, 공인된 군대나 경찰의 경우에는 사용되지 않는다. 따라서 전쟁이나 경찰력의 행사는 폭력이 아니게 된다. 이는 폭력에 대한 일반적인 개념으로 ‘사람에게 상처를 입히거나 재산에 손해를 입히는 것을 목적으로 하는 행위’로 정의하는 입장과 같다. 우리나라를 비롯한 대부분의 나라에서 일반적으로 규정하는 폭력이 그런 것이다. 이러한 폭력 개념은 윤리나 정치 또는 법에서도 가장 기본적인 관념이 되고 있는 것으로 폭력을 힘의 비합법적인 행사인 악으로 보는 전통적인 개념이다.
이런 입장은 ‘구체적인 행동만을 대상으로 한다’는 점에서 제한적이라고 비판하는 견해가 있다. 조희연․조현연, 「국가폭력․민주주의 투쟁․희생에 대한 총론적 이해」, 조희연 편, ꡔ국가폭력, 민주주의 투쟁, 그리고 희생ꡕ, 함께읽는책, 2002, 26쪽.
그러한 견해는 이러한 비판을 하면서도 달리 폭력을 정의하지 않고서, 억압의 폭력(기성 지배체제가 휘두르는 제도적 폭력, 공격적 폭력)과 해방의 폭력(필연적으로 불법적인 저항적 폭력, 생존의 방어를 위한 폭력)이란 개념을 사용하여 제도나 저항까지 폭력에 포함한다. 그러나 그런 개념을 사용하기 위해서는 전통적인 폭력 개념을 구체적인 행동에만 집중한다고 비판하는 것만으로는 충분하지 않다. 그 이유는 이러한 견해에서 사용되는 폭력이란 개념은 매우 특수하기 때문이다. 즉 종래의 일반적인 폭력 개념은 억압의 폭력이나 해방의 폭력 어디에도 포함되지 않고, 폭력이란 개념은 억압과 해방이라고 하는 정치 사회적인 맥락에서 특수하게 사용되고 있다. 그리고 위 견해는 억압의 폭력을 전쟁, 고문, 살인, 학살 등으로 상징되는 ‘국가폭력’이란 말로 이해한다. 위의 책.
그러나 그러한 국가폭력도 구체적인 행동을 뜻하는 점은 마찬가지이다. 물론 위 견해는 그런 국가폭력을 낳는 근거인 유신체제와 같은 악법을 ‘제도적 폭력’이라고 보고 있으나, 법제도까지 폭력이라고 보는 경우 폭력에 대한 더욱 엄밀한 정의가 필요하다.
폭력에 대한 구조적인 정의는 빈곤을 비롯한 사회적 부정의를 말하는 더욱 광범한 개념으로도 사용된다. 예컨대 Johan Galtung, “Violence, Peace and Peace Research," The Journal of Peace Research6(2), 1969, pp. 167-91. 특히 p. 168과 p. 173. 또한 N. Garver, “What Violence Is," in J. Rachels and F. A. Tilman (eds), Philosophical Issues: A Contemporary Introduction, New York: Harper & Row, 1972, pp. 223-8. 또한 빈곤과 관련해서는 S. Lee, 'Poverty and Violence', Social Theory and Practice 22 (1) 1996, pp. 67-82.
그것은 개인이나 제도에 의해 또는 사회 자체에 의해 가해지는 물질적인 피해는 물론 심리적인 피해까지 낳는 것을 포함한다고 주장된다. 주로 평화 연구의 영역에서 평화를 저해하는 모든 반평화적 행태나 제도를 폭력으로 보려는 이러한 태도에 대해서는 그것이 너무나도 광범하고 모호하다는 비판도 있다. C. A. J. Coady, “The Idea of Violence," Journal of Applied Philosophy 3 (1) 1986, pp 3-19.
이와 달리 폭력=테러라는 말은 최근 미국을 중심으로 하는 여러 정부가 이슬람 또는 그 일부 세력 그리고 북한 등을 비난하며 지칭하는 개념으로도 사용되고 있다. 그러면서 자신들이 행사하는 힘은 ‘폭력’이 아니라 ‘정의’라고 주장한다. 물론 이슬람 등은 미국 등이 정의라고 주장하는 것을 폭력이라고 주장한다. 이처럼 국제관계에서 사용되는 폭력 논의는 그 판단이 쉽지 않으나, 어느 측이든 자신을 폭력이라고 말하지 않고 상대방을 비난하는 개념으로 사용함은 확실하다.
이처럼 폭력이란 말의 사용에는 여러 가지가 있으나, 적어도 법적으로 폭력은 불법이므로 그 합법성이 논의될 수 없다. 물론 법적인 차원에서도 가령 범죄의 피침해자가 자력구제를 가하는 경우라든가 또는 노동자나 노동조합의 쟁의행위와 같이 그 폭력에 대한 법적 판단이 반드시 구체적인 권리를 침해하는 것으로 볼 수 없는 경우도 있을 수 있으나, 어디까지나 예외적이다. 그러나 그런 법적 평가와 무관하게 억압적 국가 권력 자체를 ‘합법적 폭력’이라고 보는 경우도 있으나, 그것에 대한 법적인 판단은 국가 권력 자체를 폭력이 아니라 합법적인 ‘권력’이라고 보는 것을 전제로 하여, 권력의 부당한 폭력적 행사에 대해서만 법은 적어도 원칙적으로 그 정당성을 인정하지 않는 것이다.
여하튼 그런 부당한 권력의 폭력적 행사에 대해 비폭력을 주장하는 것은 경우에 따라(예컨대 인도의 간디처럼) 유효할 수도 있으나, 도리어 대부분의 경우 더욱 큰 권력의 폭력적 행사를 초래할 수도 있고, 그런 경우에는 도리어 폭력적 저항(예컨대 알제리를 비롯한 대부분의 식민지 해방 투쟁)이 유효할 수 있다. 따라서 적어도 해방 전략의 차원에서 무조건적인 비폭력 주장은 반드시 유효한 것이 아니고, 폭력이 역사적으로 정당성을 갖는 경우도 얼마든지 있을 수 있다.
여하튼 이 글은 폭력에 대한 엄밀한 정의를 시도하는 것이 아니다. 그러한 정의에 대해서는 각종 사회과학 사전이나 문헌을 살펴볼 수 있으므로 이 글에서는 더 이상 다루지 않는다. 대신 이 글에서는 소렐, 벤야민, 데리다, 파농, 아렌트의 폭력 논의를 중심으로 폭력에 대한 사상을 검토하고자 하는 것이다. 그 논의의 핵심은 국가폭력과 그것에 대항하는 저항폭력이라는 것이다. 따라서 이 두 가지 개념에서 사용되는 폭력은 위에서 본 일반적인 폭력의 개념과는 다른 차원에 있다. 즉 국가 권력의 부당한 폭력의 행사와 그것에 저항하는 정당한 폭력의 행사를 대립시켜 그 범주에서만 폭력을 검토하는 것이다.
원문 : http://jbreview.jinbo.net/maynews/readview.php?table=organ&item=&no=401
VISUAL PLEASURE AND NARRATIVE CINEMA (1975) - Laura Mulvey
Originally Published - Screen 16.3 Autumn 1975 pp. 6-18
I. Introduction
A. A Political Use of Psychoanalysis
This paper intends to use psychoanalysis to discover where and how the fascination of film is reinforced by pre-existing patterns of fascination already at work within the individual subject and the social formations that have moulded him. It takes as starting point the way film reflects, reveals and even plays on the straight, socially established interpretation of sexual difference which controls images, erotic ways of looking and spectacle. It is helpful to understand what the cinema has been, how its magic has worked in the past, while attempting a theory and a practice which will challenge this cinema of the past. Psychoanalytic theory is thus appropriated here as a political weapon, demonstrating the way the unconscious of patriarchal society has structured film form.
The paradox of phallocentrism in all its manifestations is that it depends on the image of the castrated woman to give order and meaning to its world. An idea of woman stands as lynch pin to the system: it is her lack that produces the phallus as a symbolic presence, it is her desire to make good the lack that the phallus signifies. Recent writing in Screen about psychoanalysis and the cinema has not sufficiently brought out the importance of the representation of the female form in a symbolic order in which, in the last resort, it speaks castration and nothing else. To summarise briefly: the function of woman in forming the patriarchal unconscious is two-fold. She first symbolises the castration threat by her real absence of a penis, and second thereby raises her child into the symbolic. Once this has been achieved, her meaning in the process is at an end, it does not last into the world of law and language except as a memory which oscillates between memory of maternal plenitude and memory of lack. Both are posited on nature (or on anatomy in Freud's famous phrase). Woman's desire is subjected to her image as bearer of the bleeding wound, she can exist only in relation to castration and cannot transcend it. She turns her child into the signifier of her own desire to possess a penis (the condition, she imagines, of entry into the symbolic). Either she must gracefully give way to the word, the Name of the Father and the Law, or else struggle to keep her child down with her in the half-light of the imaginary. Woman then stands in patriarchal culture as signifier for the male other, bound by a symbolic order in which man can live out his phantasies and obsessions through linguistic command by imposing them on the silent image of woman still tied to her place as bearer of meaning, not maker of meaning.
There is an obvious interest in this analysis for feminists, a beauty in its exact rendering of the frustration experienced under the phallocentric order. It gets us nearer to the roots of our oppression, it brings an articulation of the problem closer, it faces us with the ultimate challenge: how to fight the unconscious structured like a language (formed critically at the moment of arrival of language) while still caught within the language of the patriarchy. There is no way in which we can produce an alternative out of the blue, but we can begin to make a break by examining patriarchy with the tools it provides, of which psychoanalysis is not the only but an important one. We are still separated by a great gap from important issues for the female unconscious which are scarcely relevant to psychoanalytic theory: the sexing of the female infant and her relationship to the symbolic, the sexually mature woman as non-mother, maternity outside the signification of the phallus, the vagina.... But, at this point, psychoanalytic theory as it now stands can at least advance our understanding of the status quo, of the patriarchal order in which we are caught.
B. Destruction of Pleasure as a Radical Weapon As an advanced representation system, the cinema poses questions of the ways the unconscious (formed by the dominant order) structures ways of seeing and pleasure in looking. Cinema has changed over the last few decades. It is no longer the monolithic system based on large capital investment exemplified at its best by Hollywood in the 1930's, 1940's and 1950's. Technological advances (16mm, etc) have changed the economic conditions of cinematic production, which can now be artisanal as well as capitalist. Thus it has been possible for an alternative cinema to develop. However self-conscious and ironic Hollywood managed to be, it always restricted itself to a formal mise-en-scene reflecting the dominant ideological concept of the cinema. The alternative cinema provides a space for a cinema to be born which is radical in both a political and an aesthetic sense and challenges the basic assumptions of the mainstream film. This is not to reject the latter moralistically, but to highlight the ways in which its formal preoccupations reflect the psychical obsessions of the society which produced it, and, further, to stress that the alternative cinema must start specifically by reacting against these obsessions and assumptions. A politically and aesthetically avant-garde cinema is now possible, but it can still only exist as a counterpoint.
The magic of the Hollywood style at its best (and of all the cinema which fell within its sphere of influence) arose, not exclusively, but in one important aspect, from its skilled and satisfying manipulation of visual pleasure. Unchallenged, mainstream film coded the erotic into the language of the dominant patriarchal order. In the highly developed Hollywood cinema it was only through these codes that the alienated subject, torn in his imaginary memory by a sense of loss, by the terror of potential lack in phantasy, came near to finding a glimpse of satisfaction: through its formal beauty and its play on his own formative obsessions.
This article will discuss the interweaving of that erotic pleasure in film, its meaning, and in particular the central place of the image of woman. It is said that analysing pleasure, or beauty, destroys it. That is the intention of this article. The satisfaction and reinforcement of the ego that represent the high point of film history hitherto must be attacked. Not in favour of a reconstructed new pleasure, which cannot exist in the abstract, nor of intellectualised unpleasure, but to make way for a total negation of the ease and plenitude of the narrative fiction film. The alternative is the thrill that comes from leaving the past behind without rejecting it, transcending outworn or oppressive forms, or daring to break with normal pleasurable expectations in order to conceive a new language of desire.
II. Pleasure in Looking/Fascination with the Human Form
A. The cinema offers a number of possible pleasures. One is scopophilia. There are circumstances in which looking itself is a source of pleasure, just as, in the reverse formation, there is pleasure in being looked at. Originally. in his Three Essays on Sexuality, Freud isolated scopophilia as one of the component instincts of sexuality which exist as drives quite independently of the erotogenic zones. At this point he associated scopophilia with taking other people as objects, subjecting them to a controlling and curious gaze. His particular examples center around the voyeuristic activities of children, their desire to see and make sure of the private and the forbidden (curiosity about other people's genital and bodily functions, about the presence or absence of the penis and, retrospectively, about the primal scene). In this analysis scopophilia is essentially active. (Later, in Instincts and their Vicissitudes, Freud developed his theory of scopophilia further, attaching it initially to pre-genital auto-eroticism, after which the pleasure of the look is transferred to others by analogy. There is a close working here of the relationship between the active instinct and its further development in a narcissistic form.) Although the instinct is modified by other factors, in particular the constitution of the ego, it continues to exist as the erotic basis for pleasure in looking at another person as object. At the extreme, it can become fixated into a perversion, producing obsessive voyeurs and Peeping Toms, whose only sexual satisfaction can come from watching, in an active controlling sense, an objectified other.
At first glance, the cinema would seem to be remote from the undercover world of the surreptitious observation of an unknowing and unwilling victim. What is seen of the screen is so manifestly shown. But the mass of mainstream film, and the conventions within which it has consciously evolved, portray a hermetically sealed world which unwinds magically, indifferent to the presence of the audience, producing for them a sense of separation and playing on their voyeuristic phantasy. Moreover, the extreme contrast between the darkness in the auditorium (which also isolates the spectators from one another) and the brilliance of the shifting patterns of light and shade on the screen helps to promote the illusion of voyeuristic separation. Although the film is really being shown, is there to be seen, conditions of screening and narrative conventions give the spectator an illusion of looking in on a private world. Among other things, the position of the spectators in the cinema is blatantly one of repression of their exhibitionism and projection of the repressed desire on to the performer.
B. The cinema satisfies a primordial wish for pleasurable looking, but it also goes further, developing scopophilia in its narcissistic aspect. The conventions of mainstream film focus attention on the human form. Scale, space, stories are all anthropomorphic. Here, curiosity and the wish to look intermingle with a fascination with likeness and recognition: the human face, the human body, the relationship between the human form and its surroundings, the visible presence of the person in the world. Jacques Lacan has described how the moment when a child recognises its own image in the mirror is crucial for the constitution of the ego. Several aspects of this analysis are relevant here. The mirror phase occurs at a time when the child's physical ambitions outstrip his motor capacity, with the result that his recognition of himself is joyous in that he imagines his mirror image to be more complete, more perfect than he experiences his own body. Recognition is thus overlaid with misrecognition: the image recognised is conceived as the reflected body of the self, but its misrecognition as superior projects this body outside itself as an ideal ego, the alienated subject. which, re-introjected as an ego ideal, gives rise to the future generation of identification with others. This mirror-moment predates language for the child.
Important for this article is the fact that it is an image that constitutes the matrix of the imaginary, of recognition/misrecognition and identification, and hence of the first articulation of the 'I' of subjectivity. This is a moment when an older fascination with looking (at the mother's face, for an obvious example) collides with the initial inklings of self-awareness. Hence it is the birth of the long love affair/despair between image and self-image which has found such intensity of expression in film and such joyous recognition in the cinema audience. Quite apart from the extraneous similarities between screen and mirror (the framing of the human form in its surroundings, for instance), the cinema has structures of fascination strong enough to allow temporary loss of ego while simultaneously reinforcing the ego. The sense of forgetting the world as the ego has subsequently come to perceive it (I forgot who I am and where I was) is nostagically reminiscent of that pre-subjective moment of image recognition. At the same time the cinema has distinguished itself in the pro- duction of ego ideals as expressed in particular in the star system, the stars centering both screen presence and screen story as they act out a complex process of likeness and difference (the glamorous impersonates the ordinary).
C. Sections II. A and B have set out two contradictory aspects of the pleasurable structures of looking in the conventional cinematic situation. The first, scopophilic, arises from pleasure in using another person as an object of sexual stimulation through sight. The second, developed through narcissism and the constitution of the ego, comes from identification with the image seen. Thus, in film terms, one implies a separation of the erotic identity of the subject from the object on the screen (active scopophilia), the other demands identification of the ego with the object on the screen through the spectator's fascination with and recognition of his like. The first is a function of the sexual instincts, the second of ego libido. This dichotomy was crucial for Freud. Although he saw the two as interacting and overlaying each other, the tension between instinctual drives and self-preservation continues to be a dramatic polarisation in terms of pleasure. Both are formative structures, mechanisms not meaning. In themselves they have no signification, they have to be attached to an idealisation. Both pursue aims in indifference to perceptual reality, creating the imagised, eroticised concept of the world that forms the perception of the subject and makes a mockery of empirical objectivity. During its history, the cinema seems to have evolved a particular illusion of reality in which this contradiction between libido and ego has found a beautifully complementary phantasy world. In reality the phantasy world of the screen is subject to the law which produces it. Sexual instincts and identification processes have a meaning within the symbolic order which articulates desire. Desire, born with language, allows the possibility of transcending the instinctual and the imaginary, but its point of reference continually returns to the traumatic moment of its birth: the castration complex. Hence the look, pleasurable in form, can be threatening in content, and it is woman as representation/image that crystallises this paradox.
III. Woman as Image, Man as Bearer of the Look
A. In a world ordered by sexual imbalance, pleasure in looking has been split between active/male and passive/female. The determining male gaze projects its phantasy on to the female form which is styled accordingly. In their traditional exhibitionist role women are simultaneously looked at and displayed, with their appearance coded for strong visual and erotic impact so that they can be said to connote to-be-looked-at-ness. Woman displayed as sexual object is the leit-motif of erotic spectacle: from pin-ups to striptease, from Ziegfeld to Busby Berkeley, she holds the look, plays to and signifies male desire. Mainstream film neatly combined spectacle and narrative. (Note, however, how the musical song-and-dance numbers break the flow of the diegesis.) The presence of woman is an indispensable element of spectacle in normal narrative film, , yet her visual presence tends to work against the development of a story line, to freeze the flow of action in moments of erotic contemplation. This alien presence then has to be integrated into cohesion with the narrative. As Budd Boetticher has put it:
"What counts is what the heroine provokes, or rather what she represents. She is the one, or rather the love or fear she inspires in the hero, or else the concern he feels for her, who makes him act the way he does. In herself the woman has not the slightest importance."
(A recent tendency in narrative film has been to dispense with this problem altogether; hence the development of what Molly Haskell has called the 'buddy movie,' in which the active homosexual eroticism of the central male figures can carry the story without distraction.) Traditionally, the woman displayed has functioned on two levels: as erotic object for the characters within the screen story, and as erotic object for the spectator within the auditorium, with a shifting tension between the looks on either side of the screen. For instance, the device of the show-girl allows the two looks to be unified technically without any apparent break in the diegesis. A woman performs within the narrative, the gaze of the spectator and that of the male characters in the film are neatly combined without breaking narrative verisimilitude. For a moment the sexual impact of the performing woman takes the film into a no-man's-land outside its own time and space. Thus Marilyn Monroe's first appearance in The River of No Return and Lauren Bacall's songs in To Have or Have Not. Similarly, conventional close-ups of legs (Dietrich, for instance) or a face (Garbo) integrate into the narrative a different mode of eroticism. One part of a fragmented body destroys the Renaissance space, the illusion of depth demanded by the narrative, it gives flatness, the quality of a cut-out or icon rather than verisimilitude to the screen.
B. An active/passive heterosexual division of labor has similarly controlled narrative structure. According to the principles of the ruling ideology and the psychical structures that back it up, the male figure cannot bear the burden of sexual objectification. Man is reluctant to gaze at his exhibitionist like. Hence the split between spectacle and narrative supports the man's role as the active one of forwarding the story, making things happen. The man controls the film phantasy and also emerges as the representative of power in a further sense: as the bearer of the look of the spectator, transferring it behind the screen to neutralise the extra-diegetic tendencies represented by woman as spectacle. This is made possible through the processes set in motion by structuring the film around a main controlling figure with whom the spectator can identify. As the spectator identifies with the main male protagonist, he projects his look on to that of his like, his screen surrogate, so that the power of the male protagonist as he controls events coincides with the active power of the erotic look, both giving a satisfying sense of omnipotence. A male movie star's glamorous characteristics are thus not those of the erotic object of the gaze, but those of the more perfect, more complete, more powerful ideal ego conceived in the original moment of recognition in front of the mirror. The character in the story can make things happen and control events better than the subject/spectator, just as the image in the mirror was more in control of motor coordination. In contrast to woman as icon, the active male figure (the ego ideal of the identification process) demands a three-dimensional space corresponding to that of the mirror-recognition in which the alienated subject internalised his own representation of this imaginary existence. He is a figure in a landscape. Here the function of film is to reproduce as accurately as possible the so-called natural conditions of human perception. Camera technology (as exemplified by deep focus in particular) and camera movements (determined by the action of the protagonist), combined with invisible editing (demanded by realism) all tend to blur the limits of screen space. The male protagonist is free to command the stage, a stage of spatial illusion in which he articulates the look and creates the action.
C.1 Sections III, A and B have set out a tension between a mode of representation of woman in film and conventions surrounding the diegesis. Each is associated with a look: that of the spectator in direct scopophilic contact with the female form displayed for his enjoyment (connoting male phantasy) and that of the spectator fascinated with the image of his like set in an illusion of natural space, and through him gaining control and possession of the woman within the diegesis. (This tension and the shift from one pole to the other can structure a single text. Thus both in Only Angels Have Wings and in To Have and Have Not, the film opens with the woman as object the combined gaze of spectator and all the male protagonists in the film. She is isolated, glamorous, on display, sexualised. But as the narrative progresses she falls in love with the main male protagonist and becomes his property, losing her outward glamorous characteristics, her generalised sexuality, her show-girl connotations; her eroticism is subjected to the male star alone. By means of identification with him, through participation in his power, the spectator can indirectly possess her too.)
But in psychoanalytic terms, the female figure poses a deeper problem. She also connotes something that the look continually circles around but disavows: her lack of a penis, implying a threat of castration and hence unpleasure. Ultimately, the meaning of woman is sexual difference, the absence of the penis as visually ascertainable, the material evidence on which is based the castration complex essential for the organisation of entrance to the symbolic order and the law of the father. Thus the woman as icon, displayed for the gaze and enjoyment of men, the active controllers of the look, always threatens to evoke the anxiety it originally signified. The male unconscious has two avenues of escape from this castration anxiety: preoccupation with the re-enactment of the original trauma (investigating the woman, demystifying her mystery), counterbalanced by the devaluation, punishment or saving of the guilty object (an avenue typified by the concerns of the film noir); or else complete disavowal of castration by the substitution of a fetish object or turning the represented figure itself into a fetish so that it becomes reassuring rather than dangerous (hence over-valuation, the cult of the female star). This second avenue, fetishistic scopophilia, builds up the physical beauty of the object, transforming it into something satisfying in itself. The first avenue, voyeurism, on the contrary, has associations with sadism: pleasure lies in ascertaining guilt (immediately associated with castration), asserting control and subjecting the guilty person through punishment or forgiveness. This sadistic side fits in well with narrative. Sadism demands a story, depends on making something happen, forcing a change in another person, a battle of will and strength, victory/defeat, all occurring in a linear time with a beginning and an end. Fetishistic scopophilia, on the other hand, can exist outside linear time as the erotic instinct is focused on the look alone. These contradictions and ambiguities can be illustrated more simply by using works by Hitchcock and Sternberg, both of whom take the look almost as the content or subject matter of many of their films. Hitchcock is the more complex, as he uses both mechanisms. Sternberg's work, on the other hand, provides many pure examples of fetishistic scopophilia.
C.2 It is well known that Sternberg once said he would welcome his films being projected upside down so that story and character involvement would not interfere with the spectator's undiluted appreciation of the screen image. This statement is revealing but ingenuous. Ingenuous in that his films do demand that the figure of the woman (Dietrich, in the cycle of films with her, as the ultimate example) should be identifiable. But revealing in that it emphasises the fact that for him the pictorial space enclosed by the frame is paramount rather than narrative or identification processes. While Hitchcock goes into the investigative side of voyeurism, Sternberg produces the ultimate fetish, taking it to the point where the powerful look of the male protagonist (characteristic of traditional narrative film) is broken in favour of the image in direct erotic rapport with the spectator. The beauty of the woman as object and the screen space coalesce; she is no longer the bearer of guilt but a perfect product, whose body, stylised and fragmented by close-ups, is the content of the film and the direct recipient of the spectator's look. Sternberg plays down the illusion of screen depth; his screen tends to be one-dimensional, as light and shade, lace, steam, foliage, net, streamers, etc, reduce the visual field. There is little or no mediation of the look through the eyes of the main male protagonist. On the contrary, shadowy presences like La Bessiere in Morocco act as surrogates for the director, detached as they are from audience identification. Despite Sternberg's insistence that his stories are irrelevant, it is significant that they are concerned with situation, not suspense, and cyclical rather than linear time, while plot complications revolve around misunderstanding rather than conflict. The most important absence is that of the controlling male gaze within the screen scene. The high point of emotional drama in the most typical Dietrich films, her supreme moments of erotic meaning, take place in the absence of the man she loves in the fiction. There are other witnesses, other spectators watching her on the screen, but their gaze is one with, not standing in for, that of the audience. At the end of Morocco, Tom Brown has already disappeared into the desert when Amy Jolly kicks off her gold sandals and walks after him. At the end of Dishonoured, Kranau is indifferent to the fate of Magda. In both cases, the erotic impact, sanctified by death, is displayed as a spectacle for the audience. The male hero misunderstands and, above all, does not see.
In Hitchcock, by contrast, the male hero does see precisely what the audience sees. However, in the films I shall discuss here, he takes fascination with an image through scopophilic eroticism as the subject of the film. Moreover, in these cases the hero portrays the contradictions and tensions experienced by the spectator. In Vertigo in particular, but also in Marnie and Rear Window, the look is central to the plot, oscillating between voyeurism and fetishistic fascination. As a twist, a further manipulation of the normal viewing process which in some sense reveals it, Hitchcock uses the process of identification normally associated with ideological correctness and the recognition of established morality and shows up its perverted side. Hitchcock has never concealed his interest in voyeurism, cinematic and non-cinematic. His heroes are exemplary of the symbolic order and the law-- a policeman (Vertigo), a dominant male possessing money and power (Marnie)--but their erotic drives lead them into compromised situations. The power to subject another person to the will sadistically or to the gaze voyeuristically is turned on to the woman as the object of both. Power is backed by a certainty of legal right and the established guilt of the woman (evoking castration, psychoanalytically speaking). True perversion is barely concealed under a shallow mask of ideological correctness--the man is on the right side of the law, the woman on the wrong. Hitchcock's skillful use of identification processes and liberal use of subjective camera from the point of view of the male protagonist draw the spectators deeply into his position, making them share his uneasy gaze. The audience is absorbed into a voyeuristic situation within the screen scene and diegesis which parodies his own in the cinema. In his analysis of Rear Window, Douchet takes the film as a metaphor for the cinema. Jeffries is the audience, the events in the apartment block opposite correspond to the screen. As he watches, an erotic dimension is added to his look, a central image to the drama. His girlfriend Lisa had been of little sexual interest to him, more or less a drag, so long as she remained on the spectator side. When she crosses the barrier between his room and the block opposite, their relationship is re-born erotically. He does not merely watch her through his lens, as a distant meaningful image, he also sees her as a guilty intruder exposed by a dangerous man threatening her with punishment, and thus finally saves her. Lisa's exhibitionism has already been established by her obsessive interest in dress and style, in being a passive image of visual perfection; Jeffries' voyeurism and activity have also been established through his work as a photo-journalist, a maker of stories and captor of images. However, his enforced inactivity, binding him to his seat as a spectator, puts him squarely in the phantasy position of the cinema audience.
In Vertigo, subjective camera predominates. Apart from flash-back from Judy's point of view, the narrative is woven around what Scottie sees or fails to see. The audience follows the growth of his erotic obsession and subsequent despair precisely from his point of view. Scottie's voyeurism is blatant: he falls in love with a woman he follows and spies on without speaking to. Its sadistic side is equally blatant: he has chosen (and freely chosen, for he had been a successful lawyer) to be a policeman, with all the attendant possibilities of pursuit and investigation. As a result. he follows, watches and falls in love with a perfect image of female beauty and mystery. Once he actually confronts her, his erotic drive is to break her down and force her to tell by persistent cross-questioning. Then, in the second part of the film, he re-enacts his obsessive involvement with the image he loved to watch secretly. He reconstructs Judy as Madeleine, forces her to conform in every detail to the actual physical appearance of his fetish. Her exhibitionism, her masochism, make her an ideal passive counterpart to Scottie's active sadistic voyeurism. She knows her part is to perform, and only by playing it through and then replaying it can she keep Scottie's erotic interest. But in the repetition he does break her down and succeeds in exposing her guilt. His curiosity wins through and she is punished. In Vertigo, erotic involvement with the look is disorienting: the spectator's fascination is turned against him as the narrative carries him through and entwines him with the processes that he is himself exercising. The Hitchcock hero here is firmly placed within the symbolic order, in narrative terms. He has all the attributes of the patriarchal super-ego. Hence the spectator, lulled into a false sense of security by the apparent legality of his surrogate, sees through his look and finds himself exposed as complicit, caught in the moral ambiguity of looking.
Far from being simply an aside on the perversion of the police, Vertigo focuses on the implications of the active/looking, passive/looked-at split in terms of sexual difference and the power of the male symbolic encapsulated in the hero. Marnie, too, performs for Mark Rutland's gaze and masquerades as the perfect to-be-looked-at image. He, too, is on the side of the law until, drawn in by obsession with her guilt, her secret, he longs to see her in the act of committing a crime, make her confess and thus save her. So he, too, becomes complicit as he acts out the implications of his power. He controls money and words, he can have his cake and eat it.
III. Summary
The psychoanalytic background that has been discussed in this article is relevant to the pleasure and unpleasure offered by traditional narrative film. The scopophilic instinct (pleasure in looking at another person as an erotic object), and, in contradistinction, ego libido (forming identification processes) act as formations, mechanisms, which this cinema has played on. The image of woman as (passive) raw material for the (active) gaze of man takes the argument a step further into the structure of representation, adding a further layer demanded by the ideology of the patriarchal order as it is worked out in its favorite cinematic form - illusionistic narrative film. The argument returns again to the psychoanalytic background in that woman as representation signifies castration, inducing voyeuristic or fetishistic mechanisms to circumvent her threat. None of these interacting layers is intrinsic to film, but it is only in the film form that they can reach a perfect and beautiful contradiction, thanks to the possibility in the cinema of shifting the emphasis of the look. It is the place of the look that defines cinema, the possibility of varying it and exposing it. This is what makes cinema quite different in its voyeuristic potential from, say, strip-tease, theatre, shows, etc. Going far beyond highlighting a woman's to-be-looked-at-ness, cinema builds the way she is to be looked at into the spectacle itself. Playing on the tension between film as controlling the dimension of time (editing, narrative) and film as controlling the dimension of space (changes in distance, editing), cinematic codes create a gaze, a world, and an object, thereby producing an illusion cut to the measure of desire. It is these cinematic codes and their relationship to formative external structures that must be broken down before mainstream film and the pleasure it provides can be challenged.
To begin with (as an ending) the voyeuristic-scopophilic look that is a crucial part of traditional filmic pleasure can itself be broken down. There are three different looks associated with cinema: that of the camera as it records the pro-filmic event, that of the audience as it watches the final product, and that of the characters at each other within the screen illusion. The conventions of narrative film deny the first two and subordinate them to the third, the conscious aim being always to eliminate intrusive camera presence and prevent a distancing awareness in the audience. Without these two absences (the material existence of the recording process, the critical reading of the spectator), fictional drama cannot achieve reality, obviousness and truth. Nevertheless, as this article has argued, the structure of looking in narrative fiction film contains a contradiction in its own premises: the female image as a castration threat constantly endangers the unity of the diegesis and bursts through the world of illusion as an intrusive, static, one-dimensional fetish. Thus the two looks materially present in time and space are obsessively subordinated to the neurotic needs of the male ego. The camera becomes the mechanism for producing an illusion of Renaissance space, flowing movements compatible with the human eye, an ideology of representation that revolves around the perception of the subject; the camera's look is disavowed in order to create a convincing world in which the spectator's surrogate can perform with verisimilitude. Simultaneously, the look of the audience is denied an intrinsic force: as soon as fetishistic representation of the female image threatens to break the spell of illusion, and erotic image on the screen appears directly (without mediation) to the spectator, the fact of fetishisation, concealing as it does castration fear, freezes the look, fixates the spectator and prevents him from achieving any distance from the image in front of him.
This complex interaction of looks is specific to film. The first blow against the monolithic accumulation of traditional film conventions (already undertaken by radical filmmakers) is to free the look of the camera into its materiality in time and space and the look of the audience into dialectics, passionate detachment. There is no doubt that this destroys the satisfaction, pleasure and privilege of the 'invisible guest,' and highlights how film has depended on voyeuristic active/passive mechanisms. Women, whose image has continually been stolen and used for this end, cannot view the decline of the traditional film form with anything much more than sentimental regret.
--Laura Mulvey, originally published - Screen 16.3 Autumn 1975 pp. 6-18
Against Human Rights
New Left Review 34, pp 115-131.(2005)
- Slavoj Žižek
Contemporary appeals to human rights within our liberal-capitalist societies generally rest upon three assumptions. First, that such appeals function in opposition to modes of fundamentalism that would naturalize or essentialize contingent, historically conditioned traits. Second, that the two most basic rights are freedom of choice, and the right to dedicate one’s life to the pursuit of pleasure (rather than to sacrifice it for some higher ideological cause). And third, that an appeal to human rights may form the basis for a defence against the ‘excess of power’.
Let us begin with fundamentalism. Here, the evil (to paraphrase Hegel) often dwells in the gaze that perceives it. Take the Balkans during the 1990s, the site of widespread human-rights violations. At what point did the Balkans—a geographical region of South-Eastern Europe—become ‘Balkan’, with all that designates for the European ideological imaginary today? The answer is: the mid-19th century, just as the Balkans were being fully exposed to the effects of European modernization. The gap between earlier Western European perceptions and the ‘modern’ image is striking. Already in the 16th century the French naturalist Pierre Belon could note that ‘the Turks force no one to live like a Turk’. Small surprise, then, that so many Jews found asylum and religious freedom in Turkey and other Muslim countries after Ferdinand and Isabella had expelled them from Spain in 1492—with the result that, in a supreme twist of irony, Western travellers were disturbed by the public presence of Jews in big Turkish cities. Here, from a long series of examples, is a report from N. Bisani, an Italian who visited Istanbul in 1788:
A stranger, who has beheld the intolerance of London and Paris, must be much surprised to see a church here between a mosque and a synagogue, and a dervish by the side of a Capuchin friar. I know not how this government can have admitted into its bosom religions so opposite to its own. It must be from degeneracy of Mahommedanism, that this happy contrast can be produced. What is still more astonishing is to find that this spirit of toleration is generally prevalent among the people; for here you see Turks, Jews, Catholics, Armenians, Greeks and Protestants conversing together on subjects of business or pleasure with as much harmony and goodwill as if they were of the same country and religion. [1]
The very feature that the West today celebrates as the sign of its cultural superiority—the spirit and practice of multicultural tolerance—is thus dismissed as an effect of Islamic ‘degeneracy’. The strange fate of the Trappist monks of Etoile Marie is equally telling. Expelled from France by the Napoleonic regime, they settled in Germany, but were driven out in 1868. Since no other Christian state would take them, they asked the Sultan’s permission to buy land near Banja Luka, in the Serb part of today’s Bosnia, where they lived happily ever after—until they got caught in the Balkan conflicts between Christians.
Where, then, did the fundamentalist features—religious intolerance, ethnic violence, fixation upon historical trauma—which the West now associates with ‘the Balkan’, originate? Clearly, from the West itself. In a neat instance of Hegel’s ‘reflexive determination’, what Western Europeans observe and deplore in the Balkans is what they themselves introduced there; what they combat is their own historical legacy run amok. Let us not forget that the two great ethnic crimes imputed to the Turks in the 20th century—the Armenian genocide and the persecution of the Kurds—were not committed by traditionalist Muslim political forces, but by the military modernizers who sought to cut Turkey loose from its old-world ballast and turn it into a European nation-state. Mladen Dolar’s old quip, based on a detailed reading of Freud’s references to the region, that the European unconscious is structured like the Balkans, is thus literally true: in the guise of the Otherness of ‘Balkan’, Europe takes cognizance of the ‘stranger in itself’, of its own repressed.
But we might also examine the ways in which the ‘fundamentalist’ essentialization of contingent traits is itself a feature of liberal-capitalist democracy. It is fashionable to complain that private life is threatened or even disappearing, in face of the media’s ability to expose one’s most intimate personal details to the public. True, on condition that we turn things around: what is effectively disappearing here is public life itself, the public sphere proper, in which one operates as a symbolic agent who cannot be reduced to a private individual, to a bundle of personal attributes, desires, traumas and idiosyncrasies. The ‘risk society’ commonplace—according to which the contemporary individual experiences himself as thoroughly ‘denaturalized’, regarding even his most ‘natural’ traits, from ethnic identity to sexual preference, as being chosen, historically contingent, learned—is thus profoundly deceiving. What we are witnessing today is the opposite process: an unprecedented re-naturalization. All big ‘public issues’ are now translated into attitudes towards the regulation of ‘natural’ or ‘personal’ idiosyncrasies.
This explains why, at a more general level, pseudo-naturalized ethno-religious conflicts are the form of struggle which best suits global capitalism. In the age of ‘post-politics’, when politics proper is progressively replaced by expert social administration, the sole remaining legitimate sources of conflict are cultural (religious) or natural (ethnic) tensions. And ‘evaluation’ is precisely the regulation of social promotion that fits with this re-naturalization. Perhaps the time has come to reassert, as the truth of evaluation, the perverted logic to which Marx refers ironically in his description of commodity fetishism, quoting Dogberry’s advice to Seacoal at the end of Capital’s Chapter 1: ‘To be a well-favoured man is the gift of fortune; but to write and read comes by nature.’ To be a computer expert or a successful manager is a gift of nature today, but lovely lips or eyes are a fact of culture.
Unfreedom of choice
As to freedom of choice: I have written elsewhere of the pseudo-choice offered to the adolescents of Amish communities who, after the strictest of upbringings, are invited at the age of seventeen to plunge themselves into every excess of contemporary capitalist culture—a whirl of fast cars, wild sex, drugs, drink and so forth. [2] After a couple of years, they are allowed to choose whether they want to return to the Amish way. Since they have been brought up in virtual ignorance of American society, the youngsters are quite unprepared to cope with such permissiveness, which in most cases generates a backlash of unbearable anxiety. The vast majority vote to return to the seclusion of their communities. This is a perfect case of the difficulties that invariably accompany ‘freedom of choice’: while Amish children are formally given a free choice, the conditions in which they must make it render the choice unfree.
The problem of pseudo-choice also demonstrates the limitations of the standard liberal attitude towards Muslim women who wear the veil: acceptable if it is their own free choice rather than imposed on them by husbands or family. However, the moment a woman dons the veil as the result of personal choice, its meaning changes completely: it is no longer a sign of belonging to the Muslim community, but an expression of idiosyncratic individuality. In other words, a choice is always a meta-choice, a choice of the modality of the choice itself: it is only the woman who does not choose to wear a veil that effectively chooses a choice. This is why, in our secular liberal democracies, people who maintain a substantial religious allegiance are in a subordinate position: their faith is ‘tolerated’ as their own personal choice, but the moment they present it publicly as what it is for them—a matter of substantial belonging—they stand accused of ‘fundamentalism’. Plainly, the ‘subject of free choice’, in the ‘tolerant’, multicultural sense, can only emerge as the result of an extremely violent process of being uprooted from one’s particular life-world.
The material force of the ideological notion of ‘free choice’ within capitalist democracy was well illustrated by the fate of the Clinton Administration’s ultra-modest health reform programme. The medical lobby (twice as strong as the infamous defence lobby) succeeded in imposing on the public the idea that universal healthcare would somehow threaten freedom of choice in that domain. Against this conviction, all enumeration of ‘hard facts’ proved ineffective. We are here at the very nerve-centre of liberal ideology: freedom of choice, grounded in the notion of the ‘psychological’ subject, endowed with propensities which he or she strives to realize. And this especially holds today, in the era of a ‘risk society’ in which the ruling ideology endeavours to sell us the very insecurities caused by the dismantling of the welfare state as the opportunity for new freedoms. If labour flexibilization means you have to change jobs every year, why not see it as a liberation from the constraints of a permanent career, a chance to reinvent yourself and realize the hidden potential of your personality? If there is a shortfall on your standard health insurance and retirement plan, meaning you have to opt for extra coverage, why not perceive it as an additional opportunity to choose: either a better lifestyle now or long-term security? Should this predicament cause you anxiety, the ‘second modernity’ ideologist will diagnose you as desiring to ‘escape from freedom’, of an immature sticking to old stable forms. Even better, when this is inscribed into the ideology of the subject as the ‘psychological’ individual, pregnant with natural abilities, you will automatically tend to interpret all these changes as the outcome of your personality, not as the result of being thrown around by market forces.
Politics of jouissance
What of the basic right to the pursuit of pleasure? Today’s politics is ever more concerned with ways of soliciting or controlling jouissance. The opposition between the liberal-tolerant West and fundamentalist Islam is most often condensed as that between, on the one side, a woman’s right to free sexuality, including the freedom to display or expose herself and to provoke or disturb men; and, on the other side, desperate male attempts to suppress or control this threat. (The Taliban forbade metal-tipped heels for women, as the tapping sounds coming from beneath an all-concealing burka might have an overpowering erotic appeal.)
Both sides, of course, mystify their position ideologically and morally. For the West, women’s right to expose themselves provocatively to male desire is legitimized as their right to enjoy their bodies as they please. For Islam, the control of female sexuality is legitimized as the defence of women’s dignity against their being reduced to objects of male exploitation. So when the French state prohibits Muslim girls from wearing the veil in school, one can claim that they are thus enabled to dispose of their bodies as they wish. But one can also argue that the true traumatic point for critics of Muslim ‘fundamentalism’ was that there were women who did not participate in the game of making their bodies available for sexual seduction, or for the social exchange and circulation involved in this. In one way or another, all the other issues—gay marriage and adoption, abortion, divorce—relate to this. What the two poles share is a strict disciplinary approach, differently directed: ‘fundamentalists’ regulate female self-presentation to forestall sexual provocation; pc feminist liberals impose a no-less-severe regulation of behaviour aimed at containing forms of harassment.
Liberal attitudes towards the other are characterized both by respect for otherness, openness to it, and an obsessive fear of harassment. In short, the other is welcomed insofar as its presence is not intrusive, insofar as it is not really the other. Tolerance thus coincides with its opposite. My duty to be tolerant towards the other effectively means that I should not get too close to him or her, not intrude into his space—in short, that I should respect his intolerance towards my over-proximity. This is increasingly emerging as the central human right of advanced capitalist society: the right not to be ‘harassed’, that is, to be kept at a safe distance from others. The same goes for the emergent logic of humanitarian or pacifist militarism. War is acceptable insofar as it seeks to bring about peace, or democracy, or the conditions for distributing humanitarian aid. And does the same not hold even more for democracy and human rights themselves? Human rights are ok if they are ‘rethought’ to include torture and a permanent emergency state. Democracy is ok if it is cleansed of its populist excesses and limited to those mature enough to practise it.
Caught in the vicious cycle of the imperative of jouissance, the temptation is to opt for what appears its ‘natural’ opposite, the violent renunciation of jouissance. This is perhaps the underlying motif of all so-called fundamentalisms—the endeavour to contain (what they perceive as) the excessive ‘narcissistic hedonism’ of contemporary secular culture with a call to reintroduce the spirit of sacrifice. A psychoanalytic perspective immediately enables us to see why such an endeavour goes wrong. The very gesture of casting away enjoyment—‘Enough of decadent self-indulgence! Renounce and purify!’—produces a surplus-enjoyment of its own. Do not all ‘totalitarian’ universes which demand of their subjects a violent (self-)sacrifice to the cause exude the bad smell of a fascination with a lethal-obscene jouissance? Conversely, a life oriented towards the pursuit of pleasure will entail the harsh discipline of a ‘healthy lifestyle’—jogging, dieting, mental relaxation—if it is to be enjoyed to the maximum. The superego injunction to enjoy oneself is immanently intertwined with the logic of sacrifice. The two form a vicious cycle, each extreme supporting the other. The choice is never simply between doing one’s duty or striving for pleasure and satisfaction. This elementary choice is always redoubled by a further one, between elevating one’s striving for pleasure into one’s supreme duty, and doing one’s duty not for duty’s sake but for the gratification it brings. In the first case, pleasures are my duty, and the ‘pathological’ striving for pleasure is located in the formal space of duty. In the second case, duty is my pleasure, and doing my duty is located in the formal space of ‘pathological’ satisfactions.
Defence against power?
But if human rights as opposition to fundamentalism and as pursuit of happiness lead us into intractable contradictions, are they not after all a defence against the excess of power? Marx formulated the strange logic of power as ‘in excess’ by its very nature in his analyses of 1848. In The Eighteenth Brumaire and The Class Struggles in France, he ‘complicated’ in a properly dialectical way the logic of social representation (political agents representing economic classes and forces). In doing so, he went much further than the usual notion of these ‘complications’, according to which political representation never directly mirrors social structure—a single political agent can represent different social groups, for instance; or a class can renounce its direct representation and leave to another the job of securing the politico-juridical conditions of its rule, as the English capitalist class did by leaving to the aristocracy the exercise of political power. Marx’s analyses pointed towards what Lacan would articulate, more than a century later, as the ‘logic of the signifier’. Apropos the Party of Order, formed after the defeat of the June insurrection, Marx wrote that only after Louis-Napoleon’s December 10 election victory allowed it to ‘cast off’ its coterie of bourgeois republicans
was the secret of its existence, the coalition of Orléanists and Legitimists into one party, disclosed. The bourgeois class fell apart into two big factions which alternately—the big landed proprietors under the restored monarchy and the finance aristocracy and the industrial bourgeoisie under the July Monarchy—had maintained a monopoly of power. Bourbon was the royal name for the predominant influence of the interests of the one faction, Orléans the royal name for the predominant influence of the interests of the other faction—the nameless realm of the republic was the only one in which both factions could maintain with equal power the common class interest without giving up their mutual rivalry. [3]
This, then, is the first complication. When we are dealing with two or more socio-economic groups, their common interest can only be represented in the guise of the negation of their shared premise: the common denominator of the two royalist factions is not royalism, but republicanism. (Just as today, the only political agent that consistently represents the interests of capital as such, in its universality, above particular factions, is the ‘social liberal’ Third Way.) Then, in The Eighteenth Brumaire, Marx dissected the makeup of the Society of December 10, Louis-Napoleon’s private army of thugs:
Alongside decayed roués with dubious means of subsistence and of dubious origin, alongside ruined and adventurous offshoots of the bourgeoisie, were vagabonds, discharged soldiers, discharged jailbirds, escaped galley slaves, swindlers, mountebanks, lazzaroni, pickpockets, tricksters, gamblers, maquereaux [pimps], brothel-keepers, porters, literati, organ-grinders, rag-pickers, knife-grinders, tinkers, beggars—in short, the whole indefinite, disintegrated mass, thrown hither and thither, which the French call la bohème; from this kindred element Bonaparte formed the core of the Society of December 10 . . . This Bonaparte, who constitutes himself chief of the lumpen proletariat, who here alone rediscovers in mass form the interests which he personally pursues, who recognizes in this scum, offal, refuse of all classes the only class upon which he can base himself unconditionally, is the real Bonaparte, the Bonaparte sans phrases. [4]
The logic of the Party of Order is here brought to its radical conclusion. In the same way that the only common denominator of all royalist factions is republicanism, the only common denominator of all classes is the excremental excess, the refuse, the remainder, of all classes. That is to say, insofar as the leader perceives himself as standing above class interests, his immediate class base can only be the excremental remainder of all classes, the rejected non-class of each class. And, as Marx develops in another passage, it is this support from the ‘social abject’ which enables Bonaparte to shift his position as required, representing in turn each class against the others.
As the executive authority which has made itself independent, Bonaparte feels it to be his task to safeguard ‘bourgeois order’. But the strength of this bourgeois order lies in the middle class. He poses, therefore, as the representative of the middle class and issues decrees in this sense. Nevertheless, he is somebody solely because he has broken the power of that middle class, and keeps on breaking it daily. He poses, therefore, as the opponent of the political and literary power of the middle class. [5]
But there is more. In order for this system to function—that is, for the leader to stand above classes and not to act as a direct representative of any one class—he also has to act as the representative of one particular class: of the class which, precisely, is not sufficiently constituted to act as a united agent demanding active representation. This class of people who cannot represent themselves and can thus only be represented is, of course, the class of small-holding peasants, who
form a vast mass, the members of which live in similar conditions but without entering into manifold relations with one other. Their mode of production isolates them from one another instead of bringing them into mutual intercourse . . . They are consequently incapable of enforcing their class interests in their own name, whether through a parliament or through a convention. They cannot represent themselves, they must be represented. Their representative must at the same time appear as their master, as an authority over them, as an unlimited governmental power that protects them against the other classes and sends them rain and sunshine from above. The political influence of the small-holding peasants, therefore, finds its final expression in the executive power subordinating society to itself. [6]
These three features together form the paradoxical structure of populist-Bonapartist representation: standing above all classes, shifting among them, involves a direct reliance on the abject/remainder of all classes, plus the ultimate reference to the class of those who are unable to act as a collective agent demanding political representation. This paradox is grounded in the constitutive excess of representation over the represented. At the level of the law, the state power merely represents the interests of its subjects; it serves them, is responsible to them, and is itself subject to their control. However, at the level of the superego underside, the public message of responsibility is supplemented by the obscene message of the unconditional exercise of power: ‘Laws do not really bind me, I can do to you whatever I want, I can treat you as guilty if I decide to do so, I can destroy you on a whim’. This obscene excess is a necessary constituent of the notion of sovereignty. The asymmetry here is structural: the law can only sustain its authority if subjects hear in it the echo of the obscene, unconditional self-assertion of power.
This excess of power brings us to the ultimate argument against ‘big’ political interventions which aim at global transformation: the terrifying experiences of the 20th century, a series of catastrophes which precipitated disastrous violence on an unprecedented scale. There are three main theorizations of these catastrophes. First, the view epitomized by the name of Habermas: Enlightenment is in itself a positive, emancipatory process with no inherent ‘totalitarian’ potential; the catastrophes that have occurred merely indicate that it remains an unfinished project, and our task should be to bring this project to completion. Second, the view associated with Adorno and Horkheimer’s Dialectic of Enlightenment and, today, with Agamben. The ‘totalitarian’ bent of Enlightenment is inherent and definitive, the ‘administered world’ is its true consequence, and concentration camps and genocides are a kind of negative-teleological endpoint of the entire history of the West. Third, the view developed in the works of Etienne Balibar, among others: modernity opens up a field of new freedoms, but at the same time of new dangers, and there is no ultimate teleological guarantee of the outcome. The contest remains open and undecided.
The starting point of Balibar’s text on violence is the insufficiency of the standard Hegelian-Marxist notion of ‘converting’ violence into an instrument of historical Reason, a force which begets a new social formation. [7] The ‘irrational’ brutality of violence is thus aufgehoben, ‘sublated’ in the strict Hegelian sense, reduced to a particular ‘stain’ that contributes to the overall harmony of historical progress. The 20th century confronted us with catastrophes—some directed against Marxist political forces, others generated by Marxist engagement itself—which cannot be ‘rationalized’ in this way. Their instrumentalization into the tools of the Cunning of Reason is not only ethically unacceptable but also theoretically wrong, ideological in the strongest sense of the term. In his close reading of Marx, Balibar nonetheless discerns an oscillation between this teleological ‘conversion-theory’ of violence, and a much more interesting notion of history as an open-ended process of antagonistic struggles, whose final ‘positive’ outcome is not guaranteed by any encompassing historical necessity.
Balibar argues that, for necessary structural reasons, Marxism is unable to think the excess of violence that cannot be integrated into the narrative of historical Progress. More specifically, it cannot provide an adequate theory of fascism and Stalinism and their ‘extreme’ outcomes, Shoah and Gulag. Our task is therefore twofold: to deploy a theory of historical violence as something which cannot be instrumentalized by any political agent, which threatens to engulf this agent itself in a self-destructive vicious cycle; and also to pose the question of how to turn the revolutionary process itself into a civilizing force. As a counter-example, take the process that led to the St Bartholomew’s Day Massacre. Catherine de Medici’s goal was limited and precise: hers was a Machiavellian plot to assassinate Admiral de Coligny—a powerful Protestant pushing for war with Spain in the Netherlands—and let the blame fall on the over-mighty Catholic family of de Guise. Thus Catherine sought to engineer the fall of both the houses that posed a menace to the unity of the French state. But the bid to play her enemies off against each other degenerated into an uncontrolled frenzy of blood. In her ruthless pragmatism, Catherine was blind to the passion with which men clung to their beliefs.
Hannah Arendt’s insights are crucial here, emphasizing the distinction between political power and the mere exercise of violence. Organizations run by direct non-political authority—Army, Church, school—represent examples of violence (Gewalt), not of political power in the strict sense of the term. [8] At this point, however, we need to recall the distinction between the public, symbolic law and its obscene supplement. The notion of the obscene double-supplement of power implies that there is no power without violence. Political space is never ‘pure’ but always involves some kind of reliance on pre-political violence. Of course, the relationship between political power and pre-political violence is one of mutual implication. Not only is violence the necessary supplement of power, but power itself is always-already at the root of every apparently ‘non-political’ relationship of violence. The accepted violence and direct relationship of subordination within the Army, Church, family and other ‘non-political’ social forms is in itself the reification of a certain ethico-political struggle. The task of critical analysis is to discern the hidden political process that sustains all these ‘non’ or ‘pre’-political relationships. In human society, the political is the encompassing structuring principle, so that every neutralization of some partial content as ‘non-political’ is a political gesture par excellence.
Humanitarian purity
It is within this context that we can situate the most salient human rights issue: the rights of those who are starving or exposed to murderous violence. Rony Brauman, who co-ordinated aid to Sarajevo, has demonstrated how the very presentation of the crisis there as ‘humanitarian’, the very recasting of a political-military conflict into humanitarian terms, was sustained by an eminently political choice—basically, to take the Serb side in the conflict. The celebration of ‘humanitarian intervention’ in Yugoslavia took the place of a political discourse, Brauman argues, thus disqualifying in advance all conflicting debate. [9]
From this particular insight we may problematize, at a general level, the ostensibly depoliticized politics of human rights as the ideology of military interventionism serving specific economico-political ends. As Wendy Brown has suggested apropos Michael Ignatieff, such humanitarianism
presents itself as something of an anti-politics, a pure defence of the innocent and the powerless against power, a pure defence of the individual against immense and potentially cruel or despotic machineries of culture, state, war, ethnic conflict, tribalism, patriarchy, and other mobilizations or instantiations of collective power against individuals. [10]
However, the question is: what kind of politicization do those who intervene on behalf of human rights set in motion against the powers they oppose? Do they stand for a different formulation of justice, or do they stand in opposition to collective justice projects? For example, it is clear that the us-led overthrow of Saddam Hussein, legitimized in terms of ending the suffering of the Iraqi people, was not only motivated by hard-headed politico-economic interests but also relied on a determinate idea of the political and economic conditions under which ‘freedom’ was to be delivered to the Iraqi people: liberal-democratic capitalism, insertion into the global market economy, etc. The purely humanitarian, anti-political politics of merely preventing suffering thus amounts to an implicit prohibition on elaborating a positive collective project of socio-political transformation.
At an even more general level, we might problematize the opposition between the universal (pre-political) human rights possessed by every human being ‘as such’ and the specific political rights of a citizen, or member of a particular political community. In this sense, Balibar argues for the ‘reversal of the historical and theoretical relationship between “man” and “citizen”’ that proceeds by ‘explaining how man is made by citizenship and not citizenship by man.’ [11] Balibar alludes here to Arendt’s insight on the condition of refugees:
The conception of human rights based upon the assumed existence of a human being as such broke down at the very moment when those who professed to believe in it were for the first time confronted with people who had indeed lost all other qualities and specific relationships except that they were still human. [12]
This line, of course, leads straight to Agamben’s notion of homo sacer as a human being reduced to ‘bare life’. In a properly Hegelian dialectics of universal and particular, it is precisely when a human being is deprived of the particular socio-political identity that accounts for his determinate citizenship that—in one and the same move—he ceases to be recognized or treated as human. [13] Paradoxically, I am deprived of human rights at the very moment at which I am reduced to a human being ‘in general’, and thus become the ideal bearer of those ‘universal human rights’ which belong to me independently of my profession, sex, citizenship, religion, ethnic identity, etc.
What, then, happens to human rights when they are the rights of homo sacer, of those excluded from the political community; that is, when they are of no use, since they are the rights of those who, precisely, have no rights, and are treated as inhuman? Jacques Rancière proposes a salient dialectical reversal: ‘When they are of no use, one does the same as charitable persons do with their old clothes. One gives them to the poor. Those rights that appear to be useless in their place are sent abroad, along with medicine and clothes, to people deprived of medicine, clothes and rights.’ Nevertheless, they do not become void, for ‘political names and political places never become merely void’. Instead the void is filled by somebody or something else:
if those who suffer inhuman repression are unable to enact the human rights that are their last recourse, then somebody else has to inherit their rights in order to enact them in their place. This is what is called the ‘right to humanitarian interference’—a right that some nations assume to the supposed benefit of victimized populations, and very often against the advice of the humanitarian organizations themselves. The ‘right to humanitarian interference’ might be described as a sort of ‘return to sender’: the disused rights that had been sent to the rightless are sent back to the senders. [14]
So, to put it in the Leninist way: what the ‘human rights of Third World suffering victims’ effectively means today, in the predominant discourse, is the right of Western powers themselves to intervene politically, economically, culturally and militarily in the Third World countries of their choice, in the name of defending human rights. The reference to Lacan’s formula of communication (in which the sender gets his own message back from the receiver-addressee in its inverted, i.e. true, form) is very much to the point here. In the reigning discourse of humanitarian interventionism, the developed West is effectively getting back from the victimized Third World its own message in its true form.
The moment human rights are thus depoliticized, the discourse dealing with them has to change: the pre-political opposition of Good and Evil must be mobilized anew. Today’s ‘new reign of ethics’, clearly invoked in, say, Ignatieff’s work, thus relies on a violent gesture of depoliticization, depriving the victimized other of any political subjectivization. And, as Rancière points out, liberal humanitarianism à la Ignatieff unexpectedly meets the ‘radical’ position of Foucault or Agamben with regard to this depoliticization: their notion of ‘biopolitics’ as the culmination of Western thought ends up getting caught in a kind of ‘ontological trap’, in which concentration camps appear as ontological destiny: ‘each of us would be in the situation of the refugee in a camp. Any difference grows faint between democracy and totalitarianism and any political practice proves to be already ensnared in the biopolitical trap’. [15]
We thus arrive at a standard ‘anti-essentialist’ position, a kind of political version of Foucault’s notion of sex as generated by the multitude of the practices of sexuality. ‘Man’, the bearer of human rights, is generated by a set of political practices which materialize citizenship; ‘human rights’ are, as such, a false ideological universality, which masks and legitimizes a concrete politics of Western imperialism, military interventions and neo-colonialism. Is this, however, enough?
Universality’s return
The Marxist symptomal reading can convincingly demonstrate the content that gives the notion of human rights its specific bourgeois ideological spin: universal human rights are effectively the right of white, male property-owners to exchange freely on the market, exploit workers and women, and exert political domination. This identification of the particular content that hegemonizes the universal form is, however, only half the story. Its crucial other half consists in asking a more difficult, supplementary question: that of the emergence of the form of universality itself. How—in what specific historical conditions—does abstract universality become a ‘fact of (social) life’? In what conditions do individuals experience themselves as subjects of universal human rights? Therein resides the point of Marx’s analysis of ‘commodity fetishism’: in a society in which commodity exchange predominates, individuals in their daily lives relate to themselves, and to the objects they encounter, as to contingent embodiments of abstract-universal notions. What I am, in terms of my concrete social or cultural background, is experienced as contingent, since what ultimately defines me is the ‘abstract’ universal capacity to think or to work. Likewise, any object that can satisfy my desire is experienced as contingent, since my desire is conceived as an ‘abstract’ formal capacity, indifferent to the multitude of particular objects that may, but never fully do, satisfy it.
Or take the example of ‘profession’: the modern notion of profession implies that I experience myself as an individual who is not directly ‘born into’ his social role. What I will become depends on the interplay between contingent social circumstances and my free choice. In this sense, today’s individual has a profession, as electrician, waiter or lecturer, while it is meaningless to claim that the medieval serf was a peasant by profession. In the specific social conditions of commodity exchange and the global market economy, ‘abstraction’ becomes a direct feature of actual social life, the way concrete individuals behave and relate to their fate and to their social surroundings. In this regard Marx shares Hegel’s insight, that universality becomes ‘for itself’ only when individuals no longer fully identify the kernel of their being with their particular social situation; only insofar as they experience themselves as forever ‘out of joint’ with it. The concrete existence of universality is, therefore, the individual without a proper place in the social edifice. The mode of appearance of universality, its entering into actual existence, is thus an extremely violent act of disrupting the preceding organic poise.
It is not enough to make the well-worn Marxist point about the gap between the ideological appearance of the universal legal form and the particular interests that effectively sustain it. At this level the counter-argument (made, among others, by Lefort and Rancière), that the form is never ‘mere’ form but involves a dynamics of its own, which leaves traces in the materiality of social life, is fully valid. It was bourgeois ‘formal freedom’ that set in motion the very ‘material’ political demands and practices of feminism or trade unionism. Rancière’s basic emphasis is on the radical ambiguity of the Marxist notion of the ‘gap’ between formal democracy—the Rights of Man, political freedoms—and the economic reality of exploitation and domination. This gap can be read in the standard ‘symptomatic’ way: formal democracy is a necessary but illusory expression of a concrete social reality of exploitation and class domination. But it can also be read in the more subversive sense of a tension in which the ‘appearance’ of égaliberté is not a ‘mere appearance’ but contains an efficacy of its own, which allows it to set in motion the rearticulation of actual socio-economic relations by way of their progressive ‘politicization’. Why shouldn’t women also be allowed to vote? Why shouldn’t workplace conditions be a matter of public concern as well?
We might perhaps apply here the old Lévi-Straussian term of ‘symbolic efficiency’: the appearance of égaliberté is a symbolic fiction which, as such, possesses actual efficiency of its own; the properly cynical temptation of reducing it to a mere illusion that conceals a different actuality should be resisted. It is not enough merely to posit an authentic articulation of a life-world experience which is then reappropriated by those in power to serve their particular interests or to render their subjects docile cogs in the social machine. Much more interesting is the opposite process, in which something that was originally an ideological edifice imposed by colonizers is all of a sudden taken over by their subjects as a means to articulate their ‘authentic’ grievances. A classic case would be the Virgin of Guadalupe in newly colonized Mexico: with her appearance to a humble Indian, Christianity—which until then served as the imposed ideology of the Spanish colonizers—was appropriated by the indigenous population as a means to symbolize their terrible plight.
Rancière has proposed a very elegant solution to the antinomy between human rights, belonging to ‘man as such’, and the politicization of citizens. While human rights cannot be posited as an unhistorical ‘essentialist’ Beyond with regard to the contingent sphere of political struggles, as universal ‘natural rights of man’ exempted from history, neither should they be dismissed as a reified fetish, the product of concrete historical processes of the politicization of citizens. The gap between the universality of human rights and the political rights of citizens is thus not a gap between the universality of man and a specific political sphere. Rather, it ‘separates the whole of the community from itself’. [16] Far from being pre-political, ‘universal human rights’ designate the precise space of politicization proper; what they amount to is the right to universality as such—the right of a political agent to assert its radical non-coincidence with itself (in its particular identity), to posit itself as the ‘supernumerary’, the one with no proper place in the social edifice; and thus as an agent of universality of the social itself. The paradox is therefore a very precise one, and symmetrical to the paradox of universal human rights as the rights of those reduced to inhumanity. At the very moment when we try to conceive the political rights of citizens without reference to a universal ‘meta-political’ human rights, we lose politics itself; that is to say, we reduce politics to a ‘post-political’ play of negotiation of particular interests.
------------------------------------------------------------------
[1] Quoted in Bozidar Jezernik, Wild Europe: The Balkans in the Gaze of Western Travellers, London 2004, p. 233.
[2] ‘The constitution is dead. Long live proper politics’, Guardian, 4 June 2005.
[3] Marx and Engels, Selected Works, vol. i, Moscow 1969, p. 83.
[4] Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. xi, Moscow 1975, p. 149.
[5] Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. xi, p. 194.
[6] Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. xi, pp. 187–8.
[7] Etienne Balibar, ‘Gewalt’: entry for Historisch-Kritisches Wörterbuch des Marxismus, vol. 5, ed. Wolfgang Fritz Haug, Hamburg 2002.
[8] Hannah Arendt, On Violence, New York 1970.
[9] Rony Brauman, ‘From Philanthropy to Humanitarianism’, South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 103, no. 2–3, Spring–Summer 2004, pp. 398–9 and 416.
[10] Wendy Brown, ‘Human Rights as the Politics of Fatalism’, South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 103, no. 2–3, p. 453.
[11] Etienne Balibar, ‘Is a Philosophy of Human Civic Rights Possible?’, South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 103, no. 2–3, pp. 320–1.
[12] Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, New York 1958, p. 297.
[13] See Giorgio Agamben, Homo sacer, Stanford 1998.
[14] Jacques Rancière, ‘Who is the Subject of the Rights of Man?’, South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 103, no. 2–3, pp. 307–9.
[15] Rancière, ‘Who is the Subject of the Rights of Man?’, p. 301.
[16] Rancière, ‘Who is the Subject of the Rights of Man?’, p. 305.
Suture : Element of the logic of the signifier
- Jacques Alain Miller
No one without those precise conceptions of analysis which only a personal analysis can provide has any right to concern himself (or herself) with it. Ladies and Gentlemen, doubtless you fully conform to the strength of that ruling by Freud in the New Introductory Lectures.
Thus, articulated as a dilemma, a question raises itself for me in your regard.
If, contravening this injunction, it is of psychoanalysis that I am going to speak, - then, by listening to someone whom you know to be incapable of producing the credentials which alone would authorize your assent, what are you doing here?
Or, if my subject is not psychoanalysis, - then you who so faithfully attend here in order to become conversant with the problems which relate to the Freudian field, what are you doing here!
And you above all, Ladies and Gentlemen the analysts, what are you doing here, you to whom Freud specifically addressed the warning not to rely on those who are not confirmed in the practice of your science, on those so-called authorities, those literary intellectuals, who bring their soup to warm at your fire, without so much as recognizing your hospitality? Even if he who reigns in your kitchens as head-chef could amuse himself by letting someone lower than the lowest kitchen boy get hold of the pot with which you are so naturally concerned since it is from it that you draw your sustenance, it was still uncertain - and I confess that I myself doubted - that you would be ready to drink in a soup merely cooked up in that way. And yet you are here. Permit me to marvel a moment at your presence, and at the privilege of your having lent me for a while that most precious of the organs at your disposal, your ear.
Which I must now attempt to justify to it, and with reasons which are at least admissible.
I will not keep you waiting. The justification lies in this, which will come as no surprise after the developments which have so enchanted your hearing at this seminar since the start of the academic year, that the Freudian field is not representable as a closed surface. The opening up of psychoanalysis is not the effect of the liberalism, the whim, the blindness even of he who has set himself as its guardian. For, if not being situated on the inside does not relegate you to the outside, it is because at a certain point, excluded from a two-dimensional topology, the two surfaces join up and the periphery or outer edge crosses over the circumscription.
That I can recognize and occupy that point is what releases you from the dilemma I presented to you, and entitles you to be listening to me today. Which will enable you to grasp, Ladies and Gentlemen, to what extent you arc implicated in my undertaking and how far its successful outcome concerns you.
Concept of the Logic of the Signifier
What I am aiming to restore, piecing together indications dispersed through the work of Jacques Lacan, is to be designated the logic of the signifier - it is a general logic in that its functioning is formal in relation to all fields of knowledge including that of psychoanalysis which, in acquiring a specificity there, it governs; it is a minimal logic in that within it are given those pieces only which arc necessary to assure it a progression reduced to a linear movement, uniformally generated at each point of its necessary sequence. That this logic should be called the logic of the signifier avoids the partiality of the conception which would limit its validity to the field in which it was first produced as a category; to correct its linguistic declension is to prepare the way for its importation into other discourses, an importation which we will not fail to carry out once we have grasped its essentials here.
The chief advantage to be gained from this process of minimisation is the greatest economy of conceptual expenditure, which is then in danger of obscuring to you that the conjunctions which it effects between certain functions are so essential that to neglect them is to compromise analytic reasoning proper.
By considering the relationship between this logic and that which I will call logician's logic, we see that its particularity lies in the fact that the first treats of the emergence of the second. and should be conceived of as the logic of the origin of logic - which is to say, chat it docs not follow its laws, but that, prescribing their jurisdiction, itself falls outside that jurisdiction.
This dimension of the archeological can be grasped most succinctly through a movement back from the field of logic itself, where its miscognition. at its most radical because closest to is recognition is effected.
That this step repeats something of that which Derrida has shown to be exemplary to phenomenology [1] will conceal to none but the most hasty this crucial difference, that here miscognition finds its point of departure in the production of meaning. We can say that it is constituted not as a forgetting, but as a repression.
To designate it I choose the name of suture. Suture names the relation of the subject to the chain of its discourse; we shall see that it figures there as the clement which is lacking, in the form of a stand-in. For, while there lacking, it is not purely and simply absent. Suture, by extension - the general relation of lack to the structure - of which it is an element, inasmuch as it implies the position of a taking-the-place-of.
It is the objective of this paper to articulate the concept of suture which, if it is not named explicitly as such by Jacques Lacan, is constantly present in his system.
Let it be absolutely clear that it is not as philosopher or philosopher's apprentice that I am speaking here - if the philosopher is as characterized by Heinrich Heine in a sentence quoted by Freud, "with his nightcaps and the tatters of his dressing-gown, patching up the gaps in the structure of the universe". But take care not to think that the function of suturation is peculiar to the philosopher: what is specific to the philosopher is the determination of the field in which he operates as a "universal structure". It is important that you realize that the logician, like the linguist. also sutures at his particular level. And, quite as much. anyone who says "I".
In order to grasp suture we must cut across what a discourse makes explicit of itself, and distinguish from its meaning, its letter. This paper is concerned with a letter - a dead letter. It should come as no surprise if the meaning then dies.
The main thread of this analysis will be Gottlob Frege's argument in Grundlagen der Arithmetik, [2] crucial here because it puts into question those terms which in Peano's axiomatic, adequate for a construction of a theory of natural numbers, are taken as primary - that is, the zero, the number, the successor. [3] This calling into question of the theory, by disintricating, from the axiomatic where the theory is consolidated, the suturing, delivers up this last.
The Zero and the One
Here then is the question posed in its most general form;
what is it that functions in the series of whole natural
numbers to which we can assign their progression?
And the answer, which I shall give at once before establishing it:
in the process of the constitution of the series,
in the genesis of progression,
the function of the subjet, miscognized is operative.
This proposition will certainly appear as a paradox to anyone who knows that the logical discourse of Frege opens with the exclusion of that which is held by empiricist theory to be essential for the passage of the thing to the unit, and of the set of units to the unit of number: that is, the function of the subject, as support of the operations of abstraction and unification.
For the unity which is thus assured both for the individual and the set, it only holds in so far as the number functions as its name. Whence originates the ideology which makes of the subject the producer of fictions, short of recognizing it as the product of its product - an ideology in which logical and psychological discourse are wedded, with political discourse occupying the key position, which can be seen admitted in Occam, concealed in Locke, and miscognized thereafter.
A subject therefore, defined by attributes whose other side is political, disposing as of powers, of a faculty of memory necessary to close the set without the loss of any of the interchangeable elements, and a faculty of repetition which operates inductively. There is no doubt that it is this subject which Frege, setting himself from the start against the empiricist foundation of arithmetic. excludes from the field in which the concept of the number is to appear.
But if it is held that the subject is not reducible, in its most essential function, to the psychological, then its exclusion from the field of number is assimilable to repetition. Which is what I have to demonstrate.
You will be aware that Frege's discourse starts from the fundamental system comprising the three concepts of the concept, the object and the number, and two relations, that of the concept to the object, which is called subsumption and that of the concept to the number which I will call assignation. A number is assigned to a concept which subsumes objects.
What is specifically logical about this system is that each concept is only defined and exists solely through the relation which it maintains as subsumer with that which it subsumes. Similarly, an object only has existence in so far as it falls under a concept, there being no other determination involved in its logical existence, so that the object takes its meaning from its difference to the thing integrated, by its spatio-temporal localization, to the real.
Whence you can see the disappearance of the thing which must be effected in order for it to appear as object - which is the thing in so far as it is one,
It is dear that the concept which operates in the system, formed solely through the determination of subsumption, is a redoubled concept: the concept of identity to a concept.
This redoubling. induced in the concept by identity, engenders the logical dimension, because in effecting the disappearance of the thing it gives rise to the emergence of the numerable.
For example, if I group what falls under the concept "child of Agamemnon and Cassandra", I summon in order to subsume them Pelops and Teledamus. To this set I can only assign a number if I put into play the concept "identical to the concept: child of Agamemnon and Cassandra". Through the effect of the fiction of this concept, the children now intervene in so far as each one is, so to speak, applied to itself - which transforms it into a unit, and gives to it the status of an object which is numerable as such. It is this one of the singular unit, this one of identity of the subsumed, which is common to all numbers in so far as they are first constituted as units.
From this can be deduced the definition of the assignation of number: according to Frege "the number assigned to the concept F is the extension of the concept identical to the concept F". Frege's ternary system has as its effect that all that is left to the thing is the support of its identity with itself, by which it is the object of the operative concept, and hence numerable.
The process that I have just set out authorizes me to conclude the following proposition, whose relevance will emerge later, - the unit which could be called unifying of the concept in so far as it is assigned by the number is subordinate to the unit as distinctive in so far as it supports the number.
As for the position of the distinctive unit, its foundation is to be situated in the function of identity which, conferring on each thing of the world the property of being one, effects its transformation into an object of the (logical) concept.
At this point in the construction, you will sense all the importance of the definition of identity which I am going to present.
This definition which must give its true meaning to the concept of number, must borrow nothing from it [4] - precisely in order to engender numeration.
This definition, which is pivotal to his system, Frege takes from Leibniz. It is contained in this statement: eadem sunt quorum unum potest substitui alteri salva veritate. Those things are identical of which one can be substituted for the other salva veritate without loss of truth. Doubtless you can estimate the crucial importance of what is effected by this statement: the emergence of the function of truth. Yet what it assumes is more important than what it expresses. That is, identity-with-itself. That a thing cannot be substituted for itself, then where does this leave truth? Absolute is its subversion.
If we follow Leibniz's argument, the failing of truth whose possibility is opened up for an instant, its loss through the substitution for one thins of another, would be followed by its immediate reconstitution in a new relation: truth is recovered because the substituted thing, in that it is identical with itself, can be the object of a judgement and enter into the order of discourse: identical with itself, it can be articulated.
But that a thing should not be identical with itself subverts the field of truth, ruins it and abolishes it.
You will grasp to what extent the preservation of truth is implicated in this identity with itself which connotes the passage from the thing to the object. Identity-with-itself is essential if truth is to be saved.
Truth is. Each thing is identical with itself.
Let us now put into operation Frege's schema, that is, go through the three-stage itinerary which he prescribes to us. Let there be a thing X of the world. Let there be the empirical concept of this X. The concept which finds a place in the schema is not this empirical concept but that which redoubles it, being "identical with the concept of X". The object which falls under this concept is X itself, as a unit. In this the number, which is the third term of the sequence, to be assigned to the concept of X will be the number 1. Which means that this function of the number 1 is repetitive for all things of the world. It is in this sense that this 1 is only the unit which constitutes the number as such, and not the 1 in its personal identity as number with its own particular place and a proper name in the series of numbers.
Furthermore, its construction demands that, in order to transform it, we call upon a thing of the world - which, according to Frege, cannot be: the logical must be sustained through nothing but itself.
In order for the number to pass from the repetition of the 1 of the identical to that of its ordered succession, in order for the logical dimension to gain its autonomy definitively, without any reference to the real, the zero has to appear.
Which appearance is obtained because truth is, Zero is the assigned to the concept "not identical with itself". In effect, let there be the concept "not identical with itself". This concept, by virtue of being a concept, has an extension, subsumes an object. Which object? None. Since truth is, no object falls into the place of the subsumed of this concept, and the number which qualifies its extension is zero.
In this engendering of the zero, I have stressed that it is supported by the proposition that truth is. If no object falls under the concept of non-identical-with-itself, it is because truth must be saved. If there are no things which are not identical with themselves, it is because non-identity with itself is contradictory to the very dimension of truth. To its concept, we assign the zero. It is this decisive proposition that the concept of not-identical-with-itself is assigned by the number zero which sutures logical discourse.
For, and here I am working across Frege's text, in the autonomous construction of the logical through itself, it has been necessary, in order to exclude any reference to the real, to evoke on the level of the concept an object not-identical-with-itself, to be subsequently rejected from the dimension of truth.
The zero which is inscribed in the place of the number consummates the exclusion of this object. As for this place, marked out by subsumption, in which the object is lacking, there nothing can be written, and if a 0 must be traced, it is merely in order to figure a blank, to render visible the lack.
From the zero lack to the zero number, the non-conceptualisable is conceptualized.
Let us now set aside the zero lack in order to consider only that which is produced by the alternation of its evocation and its revocation, the zero number.
The zero understood as a number, which assigns to the subsuming concept the lack of an object, is as such a thing - the first non-real thing in thought.
If of the number zero we construct the concept, it subsumes as its sole object the number zero. The number which assigns it is therefore 1.
Frege's system works by the circulation of an element, at each of the places it fixes: from the number zero to its concept, from this concept to its object and to its number - a circulation which produces the 1. [5]
This system is thus so constituted with the 0 counting as 1. The counting of the 0 as 1 (whereas the concept of, the zero subsumes nothing in the real but a blank) is the general support of the series of numbers.
It is this which is demonstrated by Frege's analysis of the operation of the successor, which consists of obtaining the number which follows n by adding to it a unit: n' the successor of n, is equal to n + 1, that is, ... n... (n + 1) = n'... Frege opens out the n + 1 in order to discover what is involved in the passage from n to its successor.
You will grasp the paradox of this engendering as soon as I produce the most general formula for the successor which Frege arrives at: "the Number assigned to the concept member of the series of natural numbers ending with n follows in the series of natural numbers directly after n".
Let us take a number. The number three. It will serve to constitute the concept member of the series of natural numbers ending with three. We find that the number assigned to this concept is four. Here then is the 1 of n + 1. Where does it come from? Assigned to its redoubled concept, the number 3 functions as the unifying name of a set: as reserve. In the concept of' member of the series of natural numbers ending with 3", it is the term (in the sense both of element and of final element).
In the order of the real, the 3 subsumes 3 objects. In the order of number, which is that of discourse bound by truth, it is numbers which are counted: before the 3, there are 3 numbers - it is therefore the fourth.
In the order of number, there if an addition the 0 and the 0 counts for 1. The displacement of a number, from the function of reserve to that of term, implies the summation of the 0. Whence the successor. That which in the real is pure and simple absence finds itself through the fact of number (through the instance of truth) noted 0 and counted for 1.
Which is why we say the object not-identical with itself invoked-rejected by truth, instituted-annulled by discourse (subsumption as such) - in a word, sutured.
The emergence of the lack as 0, and of 0 as 1 determines the appearance of the successor. Let there be n; the lack is fixed as which is fixed as 1: n + 1; which is added in order to give n' - which absorbs the 1.
Certainly, if the Lot n + 1 is nothing other than the counting the zero, the function of addition of the sign + is superfatory, and we must restore to the horizontal representation of the engendering its verticality: the 1 is to be taken as the primary symbol of the emergence of lack in the field of truth, and the sign + indicates the crossing, the transgression through which the 0 lack comes to be represented as 1, producing, through this difference of n to n' which you have seen to be an effect of meaning the name of a number.
Logical representation collapses this three-level construction. The operation I have effected opens it out. If you consider the opposition of these two axes, you will understand what is at stake in logical suturing, and the difference of the logic which I am putting forward to logician's logic.
That zero is a number: such is the proposition which assures logical dimension of its closure.
Our purpose has been to recognize in the zero number the suturing stand-in for the lack.
Remember here the hesitation perpetuated in the work of Bertand Russell concerning its localization (interior? or exterior to the series of numbers?).
The generating repetition of the series of numbers is sustained by this, that the zero lack passes, first along a vertical axis, across the bar which limits the field of truth in order to be represented there as one, subsequently cancelling out as meaning in each of the names of the numbers which are caught up in the metonymic chain of successional progression.
Just as the zero as lack of the contradictory object must be distinguished from that which sutures this absence in the series of numbers, so the 1, as the proper name of a number, is to be distinguished from that which comes to fix in a trait the zero of the not-identical with itself sutured by the identity with itself, which is the law of discourse in the field of truth. The central paradox to be grasped (which as you will see in a moment is the paradox of the signifier in the sense of Lacan) is that the trait of the identical represents the non-identical, whence is deduced the impossibility of its redoubling, [6] and from that impossibility the structure of repetition, as the process of differentiation of the identical.
Now, if the series of numbers, metonymy of the zero, begins with its metaphor, if the o member of the series as number is only the standing-in-place suturing the absence (of the absolute zero) which moves beneath the chain according to the alternation of a representation and an exclusion - then what is there to stop us from seeing in the restored relation of the zero to the series of numbers the most elementary articulation of the subject's relation to the signifying chain?
The impossible object, which the discourse of logic summons as the not-identical with itself and then rejects as the pure negative, which it summons and rejects in order to constitute itself as that which it is, which it summons and rejects wanting to know nothing of it, we name this object, in so far as it functions as the excess which operates in the series of numbers, the subject.
Its exclusion from the discourse which internally it intimates is suture.
If we now determine the trail as the signifier, and ascribe to the number the position of signified, the relation of lack to the trait should be considered as the logic of the signifier.
Relation of Subject and Signifier
In effect, what in Lacanian algebra is called the relation of the subject to the field of the Other (as the locus of truth) can be identified with the relation which the zero entertains with the identity of the unique as the support of truth. This relation, in so far as it is matrical, cannot be integrated into any definition of objectivity - this being the doctrine of Lacan. The engendering of the zero, from this not-identical with itself under which no thing of the world falls, illustrates this to you.
What constitutes this relation as the matrix of the chain must be isolated in the implication which makes the determinant of the exclusion of the subject outside the field of the Other its representation in that field in the form of the one of the unique, one of distinctive unity, which is called "unary" by Lacan. In algebra, this exclusion is marked by the bar which strikes the S of the subject in from of the capital A, and which is displaced by the identity of the subject onto the A, according to the fundamental exchange of the logic of the signifier, a displacement whose effect is the emergence of signification signified to the subject. Untouched by the exchange of the bar, this exteriority of the subject to the Other is maintained, which institutes the unconscious.
For: - if it is clear that the tripartition which divides (1) the signified-to-the-subject, (2) the signifying chain whose radical alterity in relation to the subject cuts off the subject from its field, and finally (3) the external field of this reject, cannot be covered by the linguistic dichotomy of signified and signifier; - if the consciousness of the subject is to be situated on the level of the effects of signification, governed, so much so that they could even be called its reflections, by the repetition of the signifier: - if repetition itself is produced by the vanishing of the subject and its passage as lack - then only the unconscious can name the progression which constitutes the chain in the order of thought.
On the level of this constitution, the definition of the subject comes down to the possibility of one signifier more.
Is it not ultimately to this function of excess that can be referred the power of thematisation, which Dedekind assigns to the subject in order to give to set theory its theorem of existence? The possibility of existence of an enumerable infinity can be explained by this, that "from the moment that one proposition is true, 1 can always produce a second, that is, that the first is true and so on to infinity". [7]
In order to ensure that this recourse to the subject as the founder of iteration is not a recourse to psychology, we simply substitute for thematisation the representation of the subject (as signifier) which excludes consciousness because it is not effected for someone, but, in the chain, in the field of truth, for the signifier which precedes it. When Lacan faces the definition of the sign as that which represents something for someone, with that of the signifier as that which represents the subject for another signifier, he is stressing that in so far as the signifying chain is concerned, it is on the level of its effects and not of its cause that consciousness is to be situated. The insertion of the subject into the chain is representation, necessarily correlative to an exclusion which is a vanishing.
If now we were to try and develop in time the relation which engenders and supports the signifying chain, we would have to take into account the fact that temporal succession is under the dependency of the linearity of the chain. The time of engendering can only be circular - which is why both these propositions are true at one and the same time, that subject is anterior to signifier and that signifier is anterior to subject - but only appears as such after the introduction of the signifier. The retroaction consists essentially of this: the birth of linear time. We must hold together the definitions which make the subject the effect of the signifier and the signifier the representative of the subject: it is a circular, though non-reciprocal, relation.
By crossing logical discourse at its point of least resistance, that of its suture, you can see articulated the structure of the subject: as a "flickering in eclipses", like the movement which opens and closes the number, and delivers up the lack in the form of the 1 in order to abolish it in the successor.
As for the + you have understood the unprecedented function which it takes on in the logic of the signifier (a sign, no longer of addition, but of that summation of the subject in the field of the Other, which calls for its annulment). It remains to disarticulate it in order to separate the unary trait of emergence, and the bar of the reject: thereby making manifest the division of the subject which is the other name for its alienation.
It will be deduced from this that the signifying chain is structure of the structure.
If structural causality (causality in the structure in so far as the subject is implicated in it) is not an empty expression, it is from the minimal logic which I have developed here that it will find its status.
We leave for another time the construction of its concept.
Notes:
[1] Edmund Husserl, L'origine de la géometrie, translation and introduction by Jacques Derrida, PUF, 1962.
[2] German text with English translation published under the title The Foundations of Arithmetic, Basil Blackwell, 1953.
[3] Our reading will not concern itself with any of Frege'g various inflections of his basic purpose, and will therefore keep outside the thematisation of the difference of meaning and reference, as well as of the later definition of the concept in terms of predication, from which is deduced its non-saturation.
[4] Which is why we must say identity and not equality.
[5] I leave aside the commentary of paragraph 76 which gives the abstract definition of contiguity.
[6] And, at another level, the impossibility of meta-language (cf by Jacques Lacan, Cahiers pour 1'analyse, No I, 1966).
[7] Dedekind, quoted by Cavailles (Philosophie mathémathique, p 124, Hermann, 1962).
--------------------------------------------------------------------
This text was published in French in Cahiers pour l'analyse 1, Winter 1966, subsequently its English version translated by Jacqueline Rose appeared in Screen 18, Winter 1978.
9쪽 4번째 줄
“사는 법을 배우기” ⇒ “사는 법을 배우기/가르치기Apprendre ? vivre”
불어에서 “apprendre”는 “배우다”는 뜻 이외에도 “가르치다”는 뜻을 함께 지니고 있는데, 이 구절은 데리다가 이 단어에 들어 있는 두 가지 의미를 모두 시사하려는 구절이므로, 이렇게 고쳐서 번역하는 것이 옳을 것 같습니다.
9쪽 4-5번째 줄
“사는 법을 배우기, 그러나 누구에게?” ⇒ “사는 법을 가르치기, 그러나 누구에게?”
여기는 “apprendre”에 담긴 “가르치다”는 뜻을 지적하는 곳이기 때문에, “배우기”를 “가르치기”로 고치는 것이 옳습니다.
9쪽 8번째 줄
“맥락 바깥에서 그것 자체만 놓고 볼 때”
⇒ “맥락 바깥에서―하지만 맥락은 항상 열린 채 남아 있으며, 따라서 오류를 낳을 수 있고 불충분하다―그것 자체만 놓고 볼 때”
여기는 원문의 줄표 사이의 내용이 누락되었습니다. 9쪽의 이 세 가지 내용은 모두 로쟈님이 지적해주신 내용입니다. 로쟈님께 감사드립니다.
10쪽 아래에서 두 번째 줄
“다른 사람의 죽음도 삶과 죽음 사이의” ⇒ “다른 사람의 죽음도. 삶과 죽음 사이의”
27쪽 주 28)
“5장 각주 291, 292 참조.” ⇒ “5장 각주 189, 190 참조.”
원주를 모두 미주로 처리하는 과정에서 각주 번호에 착오가 생겼습니다.
31쪽 10번째 줄
“왕이란 것은 하나의 사물이다.” ⇒ “왕이란 것은.”
46쪽 2번째 줄
“느낌이 주어” ⇒ “느낌이 주는”
81쪽 아래에서 두 번째 줄
“알튀세” ⇒ “알튀세르”
94쪽 두 번째 줄
“자본화한다/활용한다.” ⇒ “자본화한다/활용한다capitaliser.”
98쪽 아래에서 6번째 줄
“연금술을 분석하고, 가치들의 전도와” ⇒ “연금술을 분석하고 가치들의 전도와”
108쪽 첫 번째 줄
“분석을” ⇒ “분석”
116쪽 4번째 줄
“도상성圖上性” ⇒ “도상성圖像性”
“iconicit?”의 번역인데, “icone”이 “도상圖像”을 의미하므로 이렇게 바꾸는 게 옳습니다.
128쪽 두 번째 줄
“이것 역시 데리다의 말인데” ⇒ “이것 역시 후쿠야마의 말인데”
136쪽 아래에서 두 번째 줄
“하지만 우리가, 예고 또는” ⇒ “하지만 예고 또는”
137쪽 11번 째줄
“또한 공적인 또는 정치적인 질서” ⇒ “또한 공적이거나 정치적인 질서”
149쪽 7번 째줄
“어떤 목적의 불가피함” ⇒ “어떤 종말의 불가피함”
이것은 명백한 오역입니다. 불어의 “fin”은 “목적”과 “종말”이라는 뜻을 모두 지니고 있는데, 여기서는 “종말”이라는 뜻으로 읽어야 합니다.
161쪽 12번 째줄
“정치적 자유주의의 승리를” ⇒ “정치적 자유주의의 승리와”
164쪽 아래에서 4번째 줄
“국내적-국제적 전쟁” ⇒ “국제적 내전”
데리다는 오늘날 세계 도처에서 벌어지는 내전이 사실상 국제적인 전쟁의 성격을 띠고 있다는 것을 강조하고 있기 때문에 “국제적 내전”이라고 옮기는 것이 데리다의 뜻을 좀더 잘 전달해줄 것 같습니다.
168쪽 12번째 줄
“공표된 시장” ⇒ “공개된 시장”
169쪽 1번째 줄
“현전하는” ⇒ “현존하는”
이 책에서는 “pr?sence”를 모두 “현존”으로 번역했기 때문에, 여기도 “현전”을 “현존”으로 바꾸어야 합니다.
178쪽 4-6번째 줄
“못한다면” ⇒ “못한다 해도”
“정확하게는/정당하게는” ⇒ “정확하게/정당하게”
179쪽 7번째 줄
“고정시키는 것” ⇒ “고정시키는 정신”
180쪽 아래에서 네 번째 줄
“알튀세” ⇒ “알튀세르”
182쪽 2번째 줄
“독단주의의, 심지어 형이상학의” ⇒ “독단주의 및 심지어 형이상학의”
253쪽 6번째 줄
“finfe” ⇒ “finde”
260쪽 8번째 줄
“육신 가진 존재” ⇒ “육신을 가진 존재”
286쪽 주 189) 첫 번째 줄
“이론은” ⇒ “이 혼은”
322쪽 아래에서 세 번째 줄
“또는 양자를 분리시킬 것인가?” ⇒ “또는 어떻게 양자를 분리시킬 것인가?”
331쪽 주 218) 두 번째 줄
“원문으로는” ⇒ “원문은”
335쪽 8번째 줄
“두려운 낯섦에 대한 의지는” ⇒ “두려운 낯섦에 의지하는 것은”
337쪽 1번째 줄
“지키는 일을 수 있다.” ⇒ “지키는 일을 할 수 있다.”
341쪽 주 2) 아래에서 6번째 줄
“<<기억들―폴 드망을 위하여>>” ⇒ “<<기억들―폴 드 만을 위하여>>”
351쪽 주 93) 아래에서 두 번째 줄
“탐구되어야 하다.” ⇒ “탐구되어야 한다.”
352쪽 주 96) 두 번째 줄
“나버지” ⇒ “나머지”
354쪽 주 101) 첫 번째 줄
“끝에서 두 번째 음절은 죽었다.” ⇒ “라 페뉠티엠므는 죽었다.”
이것은 장-미셸 라바테라는 사람의 책 제목인데, 원문은 “La penulti?me est morte”입니다. 불어에서 “La penulti?me”가 “끝에서 두 번째 음절”을 뜻하기 때문에 이렇게 번역했는데, 알고 보니 이것은 말라르메의 시를 인용한 제목이었습니다. 말라르메의 시에서 “La penulti?me”가 “끝에서 두 번째 음절”이라는 뜻으로 국한되지 않는 복합적인 의미를 지니고 있기 때문에, 원어의 발음을 그대로 옮기는 것이 좋을 것 같습니다.
{사이버 맑스}에 관한 논평 - 노명우
사이버-맑스}의 저자는 "맑스주의를 혁신하는 데 도움"(41)을 주기 위해
이 책을 썼다고 밝혔다. 저자가 책을 쓴 의도를 드러낼 경우, 독자는 저자
가 의도가 과연 성공적으로 관철되었는지를 궁금해하며 책을 읽는다. "맑
스주의를 혁신"하려는 저자의 의도에 대해 저자가 아닌 독자로서 나 또한
저자의 의견은 과연 맑스주의 '혁신'에 도움을 줄 수 있을 것인가를 물으며
이 책을 읽었다.
'맑스주의 혁신'이라는 구호 속에는 두 가지 계기가 서로 충돌한다. 맑스주의가 역사화 되었다는 판단과 역사화 되었음에도 불구하고 맑스주의는 여전히 현실성을 지니고 있다는 판단이 교차할 때 맑스주의는 폐기나 교조의 대상이 아닌 혁신의 대상이 된다. 따라서 저자가 "맑스주의를 혁신하는 데 도움"을 주기 위해 이 책을 서술했다면 저자는 두 가지 계기가 현재의 지형 속에서 어떻게 교차하고 있는지를 보여줘야 하고, 폐기냐 믿음이냐의 양자택일이 아닌 새로운 전망을 독자들에게 설득해야 한다.
저자는 야심에 찬 시작을 꾀한다. 그는 자신의 의도를 이렇게 설명한다. "정보시대가 자본과 노동주체 간의 역사적 대립을 해소하기는커녕 어떻게 그 대립이 가장 거대한 전장으로 뒤바뀌는지, 새로운 첨단기술(컴퓨터, 원격 통신 그리고 유전공학)이 어떻게 형성되며, 어떻게 일반적 상품화라는 전례 없는 전 세계적 질서를 형성하는 도구로 사용되는지, 그리고 역설적으로 어떻게 이 과정에서 이전과 달리 부가 공동 분배되는 미래를 실현할 수 있는 세력들이 등장하는지 분석하고자 한다."(23) 저자의 이러한 의도는 책제목에도 잘 반영되어 있다. 책제목 {사이버-맑스}는 과거의 시점으로 환원되고 폐기 위협을 받고 있는, 아니 이미 현실 사회주의의 붕괴 이후 폐기 당한 맑스와, 맑스를 뒤로 한 채 미래를 향해서 끊임없이 전진하고 있는 정보화의 물결 사이에 다리를 놓으려는 저자의 의도를 잘 드러낸다. 그래서 이 책의 한국어판 표지에 쓰여져 있는 "{제3의 물결}에 보내는 좌파의 반론"이란 표현은 단순한 광고 문구가 아니라, 이 책이 담고 있는 정보에 대한 탁월한 압축문이다.
하지만 저자는 '맑스주의 혁신'이라는 야심에 찬 기획을 수행하기 위해서는 수많은 적들을 물리쳐야 한다. 더구나 그 적들은 맑스주의 외부에만 있지 않고, 내부에도 있다. 맑스주의를 둘러싼 현재의 이론적 정세는 이렇다. 신자유주의는 "국가사회주의의 몰락은 맑스주의의 붕괴를 최종 선언"했다고 주장한다. 신자유주의가 맑스주의 외부의 적이라면, 저자에 의해 '포스트 맑스주의'라는 딱지를 부여받은 맑스주의는 외부의 적 못지 않게 위험한 내부의 적이다. 왜냐하면 포스트 맑스주의는 전통적 맑스주의의 이론에 내재한 계급 환원론과 '총체성' 지향 을 문제삼으며 맑스주의를 혁신하지만 그 혁신은 잘못된 것으로 저자에 의해 판명된다. 왜냐하면 포스트주의자들은 "미디어와 대중문화를 언급할 때에도 자본주의적 구조조정의 어두운 측면을 노골적으로 경시"하고 "대중문화를 둘러싼 거품뿐이 열광에 아첨"하기 때문이다.
저자는 맑스주의의 폐기를 주장하는 맑스주의의 과거에 대한 우파적 해석과 전유, 그리고 계급노선을 순치 시키는 포스트 맑스주의의 맑스주의 역사해석 양자에 거리를 둔다. 그가 거리를 두는 맑스주의의 과거를 해석하는 두 가지 입장은 저자가 보기에 '참된 맑스'와의 대화가 아니라 부재 하는 맑스주의의 유령을 다루고 있다는 점에서 공통적이다. 즉 저자에게 지금까지 제기된 맑스주의를 역사화 하려는 모든 경향은 "맑스주의의 유령과 적대적인 대화"(42)의 산물이라는 것이다. 맑스주의의 유령과 대화하는 대신, 저자는 맑스주의를 혁신하기 위해 뉴미디어와 대화하려 한다. 뉴미디어로 인한 사회적 조건의 변화에 주목하여 맑스주의의 혁신을 모색하는 것은 저자가 보기에 맑스적이면서 동시에 비맑스적이다. 이러한 모색은 19세기 당시 최첨단 정보산업이었던 {라인신문}의 편집장이었던 맑스를 염두에 둘 때 철저히 맑스적이다. 단지 21세기의 맑스는 올드 미디어가된 신문이 아닌, 21세기의 최첨단 정보산업의 성과를 이용하려하다는 점에서 맑스와 다른 시도를 꾀할 뿐이다.
저자는 정보혁명에 대응하는 맑스주의의 3가지 입장을 이렇게 분류한다. (1) 자본주의를 필연적으로 패배시킴으로써 절정에 다다를 변증법적 드라마의 주인공으로 과학기술을 바라보는 과학적 사회주의 (2) 기술이 자본주의의 지배적 도구라는 점에 초점을 맞추는 네오 러다이트 (3) 기술의 중재를 통해서 노동과 자본이 서로 화해할 가능성을 내다보는 포스트포드주의(94)
과학적 사회주의를 주장하는 현대의 저자로 저자가 지적하는 만델은 저자에 의해 탈산업주의자들과 은밀한 공감대를 형성하고 있다는 이유로 비판된다. "만델이 보여준 자동붕괴론적 맑스주의는 상대방의 이론에 담긴 가정을 그대로 반영하고 있다. 다만 과학적 기술혁신이 온화하고 진화된 미래를 가져오리라는 전망에 대해서만 의견이 엇갈릴 뿐이다."(107) 만델류의 객관주의적 분석은 "노동이 욕구와 욕망에 따라 움직이는 살아 있는 주체라는 점뿐만 아니라, 이 주체가 적어도 기계 속에 구현된 죽은 노동만큼 복잡하고 다양하게 역동적인 변화를 겪는다는 점도 거의 이해하지 못하며, 자본주의가 주로 이런 집합적 주체의 에너지를 가둬둔 채 억누르면서 발전해 나아간다는 점도 거의 이해하지 못한다"(109)는 것이다.
반면 네오 러다이트들은 정보사회를 가능하게 하는 기술 그 자체를 지배와 동의어로 봄으로써 "죽은 노동으로 산 노동을 지배하는 자본의 능력을 과대 평가"하기에 "궁극적으로 자기패배를 불러올 한계"(121)를 지니고 있다. 네오 러다이트가 기술을 두려워한다면, 포스트 포드주의적 입장은 기술을 너무나 신뢰하기에 저자에 의해 공격된다. 즉 포스트 포드주의적 입장을 견지하는 세력들은 "자본의 새로운 기술이 지닌 억압적인 힘에 절망하기보다, 그 기술의 해방적 잠재력에 매혹되는 문"으로 들어섰다는 것이다. 맑스주의를 구원하기 위해, 맑스주의의 역사를 해석하는 모든 입장을 비판하는 저자가 찾아낸 유일한 탈출구는 자율주의적 노선이다.
현재를 전유하기 위해 혁신의 전통을 비판하는 것은 필요하다. 하지만 혁신의 전통을 비판하려는 맑스주의자가 경계해야 할 점이 있다. 즉 맑스주의 진영 내부의 상호비판이 치열해질 때, 맑스주의의 명백한 적인 자본보다 자신과 다른 판단을 내리는 다른 맑스주의가 강력하고 시급한 적으로 부각되는 아이러니이다. 맑스주의의 혁신은 맑스주의 내부에서 되풀이되어온 이 아이러니의 극복 또한 요구된다. 하지만 저자는 내부의 잘못된 해석에 너무나 많은 관심을 할애한 나머지 아이러니에서 빠져 나올 길을 찾지 못한다. 그는 너무나 많은 맑스주의 내부의 적을 만들어놓았다. 그 이후 저자는 힘든 싸움을 벌인다. 저자는 한편으로는 맑스주의의 잘못된 혁신을, 그리고 다른 한편으로는 자본을 상대로 각각의 문제점을 지적해야 하기 때문이다. 맑스주의의 현재성과 혁신을 다루고 있는 책은 맑스주의를 무역사적으로 옹호하거나, 맑스주의를 시대적 변화의 속도를 근거 삼아 폐기하려는 주장보다 어려운 길을 걷는다. 과연 저자는 이 위험한 경계에서 벌이는 싸움에 성공했는가?
이 책의 정당한 문제제기와 참신한 해석 시도와 야심에 찬 의도는 책의 중반 이후, 유일한 해결의 길로서 자율주의적 맑스주의를 선택하고, 그 유일한 선택의 정당성을 주장하기 시작하는 순간부터 설득력을 급속히 상실한다. 자율주의적 맑스주의의 틀을 통한 맑스주의의 혁신을 독자에게 설득하는 저자의 호흡은 빠르지만, 아쉽게도 "저자의 손은 끝까지 침착하지 못하고 있다." 저자는 자율주의적 맑스주의 해석이 유일한 혁신의 길임을 의심하지 않고, 확신에 찬 목소리로 숨가쁘게 이렇게 말한다. "그러므로 나는 자율주의적 맑스주의가 정보혁명을 전복적으로 이해할 수 있도록 해주는 대항해석이라고 주장하고 싶다(사실상, 맑스를 능동적이고 창의적으로 해석한다는 점에서 자율주의자들의 저서들은 읽을 만한 가치가 있다) 이런 대항 해석은 근본적으로 대안적인 전망을 통해 공동체와 커뮤니케이션을 바라보면서, 컴퓨터화된 자본주의에 맞설 수 있는 21세기의 코뮤니즘을 구축하는데 기여할 것이다."(147)
자율주의적 노선의 유일한 정당성을 주장하기 위해 맑스주의 내부의 다양한 혁신 노력과 거리를 둔 것처럼, 자율주의적 맑스주의 해석을 '정보시대'의 유일한 '대항해석'이라는 주장을 저자가 펼치자마자 저자의 주장은 진리의 보증물을 표현해주는 '당파성'이라는 기호가 '올바른 해석'으로 바뀌었을 뿐, 구좌파의 당파성 논쟁과 유사한 논쟁의 구도로 말려 들어간다. 자율주의적 맑스주의가 정보시대에 대한 맑스주의의 대응이라는 주장과, 유일한 올바른 해석이라는 주장은 확실히 다르다. 저자는 점점 후자의 길을 택한다. 저자가 후자의 길을 택하면 택할수록, 맑스주의 내부에는 무수히 잘못된 혁신의 길과 하나의 정당한 혁신의 길 사이의 대립만 명료해진다.
정보기술의 발전에 따라 맑스주의가 혁신되어야 한다는 저자의 주장은 충분히 설득력을 지닌다. 하지만 저자의 설득력은 자율주의적 맑스주의가 유일한 대안이라는 배타적 주장이 첨단 정보기술로 인한 새로운 운동의 가능성에 대한 일방적 주장이 맞물리면서 현실성을 상실해간다. 저자는 '사회적 노동자'들이 쌍방향 미디어의 출현으로 인한 새로운 커뮤니케이션 기술을 대안적 저항운동으로 사용하려는 시도들에 주목한다. 저자는 새로운 커뮤니케이션 기술이 대안적으로 사용되는 예들을 '적극적인 시청자' 분석에서부터, 대안적이고 자율적인 미디어의 발전, 즉 라디오 행동주의, 게릴라 비디오, 퍼블릭 엑세스 케이블 운동, "낡은 픽업트럭의 전구소켓에 노트북을 꽂아 성명서를 입력하는 부사령관 마르코스"(336)에 이르기까지 섬세하게 찾아내고, 이 사례들을 자신의 주장의 정당성의 증거로 제시한다. 물론 저자는 인터넷의 대안적 사용가능성에 대한 탈산업주의자들의 과장된 견해와 자신을 구별하기 위해 사이버 스페이스의 정치성을 기술적 측면에서 찾지 않고, "지상에서 벌어지는 투쟁들을 서로 눈으로 확인하고 연결할 수 있는 토대를 마련해주는 미디어"(275)이기 때문이라 한정을 짓지만, 저자의 설득력은 점점 떨어진다.
저자는 쉬지 않고 인터넷의 대안적 사용가능성에 대한 사례를 수집하고 제시한다. "오늘날 다양한 투쟁결절점들은 이런 활동을 통해 전지구적 차원에서 수평적으로 연결되고 있다. 이들은 기술적 노하우와 장비를 서로 이전시켜줄 뿐만 아니라, 정치적 분석 토론 지지를 중계해주기도 한다. 캘리포니아의 저출력 방송국들은 아이티 프린스 항에 라디오 방송국을 세우려는 활동가들을 지원하고 있다. 벤쿠버의 비디오 활동가들은 니카라과의 대중교육을 전담한다. 영국 뉴베리의 고속도로 항의자들은 나이지라 웅고니랜드의 민주화 운동가들에게 시위를 지지하는 팩스를 받았다. 한편 유럽의 환경 활동가들은 켄 사로-위와의 사형선고에 항의해 쉘오일에 대량의 전자우편을 보내기도 했다. 바로 이것이 투쟁세력 재구성의 커뮤니케이션적 연결이다."(316) 저자가 제시하는 사례들은 분명 주목받을 만한 새로운 경향인 것은 사실이다. 하지만 다양한 대항집단이 인터넷을 혁명적으로 이용하고 있는 것이 사실인 만큼 정보격차(Digital Divide)도 사실이다. 저자는 정보격차를 증거로 삼아, 인터넷의 대안적 사용가능성을 비판하는 모든 시도들 정보사회의 가능성에 주목하지 못한 채 계급 불평등만을 되풀이하는 낡은 좌파의 푸념으로 치부한다.
저자는 "인터넷은 부분적으로 성별, 인종, 연령에 따라, 특히 소득에 따라 개인용 컴퓨터, 모뎀, 전문 기술을 향한 접근가능성이 차별된다는 인구통계학적 한계"(267)에 대해서 눈을 감은 채, "1991년 나이키가 농구황제 마이클 조던에게 그가 광고를 한 신발을 만들기 위해서 고된 일을 한 젊은 인도네시아 여성들 3만 명의 연간 수입을 합친 것보다 더 많은 돈을 홍보비용으로 지불"한다는 사실에 항의하기 위해 "인터넷을 사용해 전 세계 각지에서 나이키 본사로 '전화공격'"을 감행한 사실과 맥도널드 햄버거 체인점의 저임금노동관행, 아이들을 겨냥한 광고, 우림 파괴, 동물들에게 가한 범죄에 항의하는 '맥도널드에 저항한 2인조'에 의해 주도되어 전 세계 맥도널드 체인점의 홈페이지에서 이뤄진 시위와 방해작전에만 주목한다. 이토록 {제3의 물결}에 대한 좌파의 반론은 점점 후반부로 가면 갈수록 {제3의 물결}에 대한 좌우파 혼성 합창처럼 들린다. 저자는 뉴미디어를 통해 가능한 일을 너무 믿고 있는 것일까? 아니면 이 책을 읽고 있는 나는 뉴미디어의 가능성을 지나치게 회의하고 있는 것일까? 그 질문에 대한 대답은 또 다른 독자에게 돌린다.
댓글 목록
관리 메뉴
본문
번역글은 <모더니즘 이후 미술의 화두>(윤난지 편)라는 책에 있다. (이 책은 번역이 훌륭하지는 않지만, 현대 인문학의 주요 논문들을 잘 추려서 모아 놓았다는 점에서 어느 정도 소장 가치가 있다)부가 정보